Introduction
History is replete with examples of financial crisis; they appear to be an intrinsic feature of market-oriented credit and financial systems. In recent years, the march of globalisation and concomitant increases in capital and trade flows has led to increased volatility in international financial markets, and as a result, financial crises have become increasingly common across the globe. While each financial crisis is no doubt distinct, they also share striking similarities with one another, and an examination of the longer historical record finds stunning quantitative and qualitative parallels. This begs the question; can previous recessions provide us with lessons on how to handle the current financial crisis?
The current financial crisis is the first major financial crisis of the 21st Century, and it has developed rapidly, becoming increasingly virulent, causing widespread disruption to both industrial and emerging economies across the globe. Nevertheless, it follows a well-trodden path laid down by centuries of financial folly, and to understand this crisis and determine optimal policy responses, many analysts have compared the current turmoil to the collapse of Japan’s bubble economy in the early 1990s and the need to prevent the kind of prolonged slump that hit Japan.
Similar to the current global financial crisis, Japan’s ‘lost decade’ began with stock market and real estate bubbles. At the beginning of the 1990s these speculative asset bubbles began to burst, first with a reduction in the Nikkei Stock Index, followed in early 1992 by a fall in land prices (Amyx, 2004). From its 1989 peak of 38,916, the Nikkei Stock Index average fell by 63% during the 1990s (McCurry, 2008). Similarly, land prices slumped; commercial land values fell by roughly 80% in a decade, a far cry from the days when the grounds of the Imperial Palace in Tokyo were rumoured to be worth more than all the real estate in California (McCurry, 2008). Both companies and individuals were rendered unable to repay loans secured by these assets, leaving the nation’s banks with an enormous burden of non-performing loans, triggering a banking crisis (Amyx, 2004). The result was more than a decade of low growth, deflation, and output persistently below potential.
The Japanese economic model had gone horribly wrong, and recovery failed to materialize. At first, the Japanese Government’s strategy was forbearance, more than six years passed from the onset of severe financial distress before the Government initiated aggressive measures to tackle the bad debt problem and instigate fundamental financial reforms (Amyx, 2004). In 1996, following the bankruptcy of several specialised housing loan companies, known as jusen, the Government made its first capital injection to purchase assets from ailing lenders (Nanto, 2008). In total the Japanese Government pumped $495 billion (¥60 trillion yen), or 12% of GDP, under five different bailout packages, into the banking sector (Nanto, 2008). The motive behind the Government’s capital injections was that if it could keep banks and lenders operating their profits from operations and capital gains from equity holdings could fund the write-offs of bad loans (McCurry, 2008). However, the bailout packages came at a cost. Free to lend again, banks simply used funds to keep countless ‘zombie’ companies afloat. Between 1995 and 2003, Japan’s banks wrote off a cumulative total of $318 billion (¥37.2 trillion) in non-performing loans, but new ones appeared so fast that the total outstanding amount kept increasing and peaked in March 2002 at $330 billion (¥43.2 trillion) or 8.4% of total lending (Nanto, 2008). The Bank of Japan was similarly unresponsive to begin with, waiting seventeen months before cutting interest rates, and did not bring it down to 0% until 2001 (McCurry, 2008). Nevertheless, interest rates were eventually slashed, and remained at 0% for almost six years (Fackler, 2008).
Overcoming the crisis in Japan took a combination of capital injections, new laws and regulations, quantitative-easing, stronger oversight, a reorganization of the banking sector, and a constantly low interest rate. The process took more than a decade and full recovery, given the current economic environment, remains elusive. The Nikkei Stock Index is still 70% off its 1989 peak, and property prices are at roughly 40% of their 1990 values (McCurry, 2008). However, one of the silver linings of adversity is that it teaches us valuable lessons, so what lessons does Japan’s experience offer for the rest of the world?
Literature Review
Overview
This report reviews the major actions of the Japanese Government in dealing with its crisis, highlighting some of the lessons learned from their experience. It will then proceed to determine whether these lessons are being applied today, assessing if there is any evidence of an improved response. To tackle this core thesis, it is necessary to examine the literature related to five distinct aspects of the Japanese financial crisis. This review will begin with literature detailing the circumstances and effects of the Japanese financial crisis and then progress to analyse the approaches and tools employed by regulators in response to the crisis. Section III will then draw on literature examining the key lessons distilled from the Japanese financial crisis. Subsequently, the paper will examine whether these lessons are applicable to different financial crises. Finally, section V will assess whether any of the lessons obtained from Japan’s experience are being employed in response to the current financial predicament, concentrating on the responses of the US and UK.
I.I Literature on the circumstances and effects of the Japanese financial crisis
The first step in assessing the responses to the Japanese crisis is understanding the nature of the meltdown and its root causes. There is a high degree of consensus on the nature of the crisis; the collapse of the bubble economy of the 1980’s and the fall of real estate prices. There are many examples of literature detailing these issues. For example Vogel (2006), Cooper (2001), Amyx (2004), Nakaso (2001) and Nanto (2008) focus on these twin aspects and the implications held for the Japanese economy. Nanto is particularly informative, producing a comprehensive portrait of the pre-crisis bubble period and the effect of the ‘burst’ on the financial sector. Cooper expands upon this issue, providing a broader overview of the effects of the crisis, incorporating GDP growth rate, employment, living standards, and foreign trade balances. He highlights that the crisis severely crippled the Japanese economy, bringing their growth rate below that of any OECD country. Moreover, there is a wealth of insightful commentary into the nature of the crisis from Japanese and international press coverage focusing on the core effects.
However, there is more disagreement amongst analysts regarding the underlying causes of these economic problems. Most serious analysts acknowledge that Japan’s economic problems were caused by both macroeconomic policy failures and structural inefficiencies, but they differ in the relative weight they ascribe the two factors. One school of thought argues that Japan’s macroeconomic policies played a more important role. Posen (2004) argues that the burst in the bubble was caused by inappropriate concretionary fiscal and monetary policies in the late 1980’s. He further argues that when the Government introduced fiscal stimulus to boost demand, it was too little too late. Similarly Krugman (1999) supports this school of thought, but emphasises the role of monetary policy. He argues that the Japanese economy entered a liquidity trap; at very low interest rates individuals will hold all additions to the supply of money, thus rendering monetary policy ineffective.
Another group of analysts argue that structural rigidities within the Japanese economy were more important than these macroeconomic policy failures. These economists view the bubble economy as a symptom of underlying structural problems rather than a cause of the prolonged stagnation (Vogel, 2006). One such economist, Richard Katz (1998), argues that Japanese economic problems are rooted in its ‘dual economy’. He asserts that the pre crisis Japanese economy could be regarded as two separate entities; one was highly efficient and competitive whilst the other was inefficient and survived because of protective government regulations. According to Katz, the Japanese economy was able to thrive up until the 1990s because the competitive part of the dual economy propped up the non-competitive segment. He uses the example of car manufacturers, who would buy glass, steel and other components from domestic manufacturers at higher prices than more efficient foreign suppliers. Katz suggests that over time the Government shifted its emphasis from the competitive to the protected sector and with the sharp appreciation of the yen in the 1980s, the efficient sectors could no longer bankroll the system without losing their competitive edge. Masahiko Aoki (2000) puts this point slightly differently, contending that Japan’s fundamental dilemma was that competitive sectors naturally drifted away from the Government’s industrial policy framework while less competitive sectors relied increasingly heavily on government support.
Vogel (2006) stresses a different type of structural problem, a chronic excess of savings due to an inadequate social safety net and the lack of a comprehensive retirement program. This high level of saving fuelled investment, but also implied suppressed consumption. The Japanese economy was left with a stubborn investment savings gap and could not shift from investment driven to consumption driven growth (Vogel, 2006). Scheade (1996) puts forward a different argument, suggesting that the crisis was more the result of the inappropriate design of the regulatory system. His argument is based around the premise that the Japanese financial system and its regulatory structure did not evolve after the post-war period of rapid growth, 1950 - 1973. He states that the system was characterized by collusive regulation, referred to as dango gyose, and administrative guidance, resulting in an entanglement of regulators and regulates and consequently neither party were interested in disclosure or rule enforcement, as well as the high degree of fraud (Scheade, 1996).
This debate identifies a central piece of the story, it is clear that both policy failures and structural inefficiencies were to blame for the economic malaise. Therefore in assessing Japan’s responses to the economic problems it is important to consider both issues.
I.II Literature examining and analysing the responses of Japanese authorities
There is a vast array of sources detailing the Japanese Government’s financial reforms and recovery efforts. Cooper (2001) has produced a comprehensive report examining the core aspects of the Government’s response; fiscal measures, monetary policy, banking reform and other structural changes. Further sources build upon this level of detail and analyse a specific area of the Government’s approach. Nanto (2008), for instance, focuses on the five bailout packages and other sources of fiscal stimulus. Similarly, Nakaso (2001) provides an exceptionally detailed overview of the nature of the banking reform up to March 2000, utilising his prior position as a manager of the Bank of Japan.
Analysis of the tools employed by the Japanese regulators is typically critical. Most commentators agree that intervention took far too long to materialise. Amyx (2004) highlights this issue, stating that the Government’s delayed response translated into lost output and enormous fiscal outlays. Similarly, Vogel (2006) supports this view, stressing that the Bank of Japan moved too slowly and too gradually to lower interest rates. He also notes that when they eventually did lower interest rates to zero, they still remained bound by their post war fixation with combating inflation. Hwang and Schaefer (2002) examine the factors impeding the implementation of policies to address Japan's economic problems and attempt to answer why intervention was so late. They highlight factors such as bureaucratic intransigence, lack of political will, powerful interest groups with much to lose under reform, and the relatively minor impact of the crisis on the daily lives of the average Japanese citizen.
Likewise, many analysts regard the Government’s financial reforms and recovery efforts, once implemented, as ineffective. A number of authors attribute much of the economy’s disappointing performance to “exceptionally poor monetary policymaking” (Bernanke, 2000, p. 150). Additionally, Kuttner and Posen (2002) find that Japanese fiscal policy was contractionary over much of the 1990s, and attribute part of the protracted downturn to insufficient fiscal stimulus. Moreover, Amyx’s (2004) statistically based analysis asserts that policy remedies were unsuccessful. Kobayashi (2009) supports this contention with his conclusion that the fiscal stimulus packages proved ineffective because the Government did not pursue a serious policy effort to make banks dispose of their non-performing loans. Furthermore, Katz (2003) supports this line of thought with his argument that certain reforms, such as aggressive tax reforms, only exacerbated Japan’s economic woes because they reduced households’ capacity to consume.
The combination of timid monetary policy and counterproductive fiscal policy resulted in a macroeconomic strategy that failed to restore aggregate demand, defeat deflation, and return the Japanese economy to growth (Sheard, 2008). An examination of the Japanese Government’s responses therefore suggests that the crisis could have been handled better. Thus, it ensues that lessons can be derived on how to better tackle a crisis of this nature.
I.III Literature examining the key lessons derived from Japan’s experience
The context of the current financial climate has led many economists to examine what lessons can be derived from Japan’s policy failures. As Blanchard notes “this may not be a bad time to assess the lessons from the Japanese full experiment” (Blanchard, 2000, p. 185).
Drawing on the findings of many analysts, one of the clearest lessons emerging from studies of Japan’s banking crisis is that action should have been swifter. The delayed response by Japanese authorities to the bad debt problem only exacerbated the issue and escalated the costs of recovery, a mistake that should serve as a key lesson for the current crisis (Amyx, 2004). Sheard (2008) supports this view, asserting that the Japanese Government acted far too slowly and timidly on all accounts. One way in which he illustrates this view is with the example that it was not until 1998 that the deposit guarantee was funded and an institutional infrastructure was implemented to deal with the troubled assets (Sheard, 2008).
Japan’s five bank bailout packages also hold some lessons for today’s global policymakers. Hoshi (2008) identifies one such lesson, asserting that recapitalization attempts were nowhere near large enough to solve the capital shortage problems of Japanese banks in the long run. By 2005 cumulative losses totalled over ¥96 trillion, roughly 19% of GDP, clearly dwarfing the amount injected by Japanese authorities (Hoshi, 2008). He concludes this point with the view that Japan’s experience suggests that small and repeated capital injections are, at best, only temporary fixes. Kobayashi (2008a) also highlights a similar lesson related to Japan’s capital injections. He suggests that capital injections are unlikely to succeed in eradicating payment uncertainty, but if fiscal stimulus is to work then stringent asset evaluation is necessary. Moreover, Nanto (2008) documents that when Japan announced its first financial bailout package, it placed stringent conditions on the assistance that banks were unwilling to accept. The net result was that the banks ignored the package and tried to bolster their balance sheets by not lending.
Further lessons can be derived from Japan’s recapitalization policies. Hoshi (2008), for instance identifies that Governments attempting to implement their own recapitalization policies must conduct due diligence on the financial institutions receiving public funds. In Japan, many small but important regional banks were recapitalized, only to eventually fail (Hoshi, 2008). Additionally, banks that receive public funds should not be forced to lend to small and medium sized firms. As the goal of recapitalization is to enable banks to continue to extend credit, the Japanese Government opted to require banks to lend to small and medium sized firms, but this policy kept credit open to many insolvent ‘zombie’ firms (Hoshi, 2008). Hoshi concludes that both these mistakes contributed to Japan’s subsequent decade of economic malaise.
Regarding monetary policy, Kobayashi (2008b) makes the point that it should not be heralded as a perfect solution in an insolvency crisis. In this respect he adopts a similar view to that of Nobel laureate, Professor Lucas, who remarks that “monetary policy should concentrate on the one thing it can do well; control inflation. It can be hard to keep this in mind in financially chaotic times, but I think it is worth a try” (Wall Street Journal, September 19, 2007). This view is further supported by Daniel Leigh in his IMF paper (2009). Other scholars, however, draw less sceptical lessons from Japan’s monetary policies. Sheard (2008), Woodford (2008), and Posen (2009) argue that quantitative-easing was an effective strategy for addressing deflation, despite the policy’s shortcomings. As Woodford points out, a lesson to be absorbed is that central banks should signal that they are expanding the balance sheet consistent with their calculation of how much money should be in the economy after re-flation is successful (Woodford, 2008).
Furthermore, there are a number of additional lessons to be taken from Japan’s experiences. Kobayashi (2008a), for instance, highlights that debt restructuring is absolutely necessary to prevent a vicious cycle and that public asset management companies may need to be established to prevent debt deflation. Similarly, Kanaya and Woo (2000) document that Japanese regulatory authorities needed to take a proactive attitude towards supervision, and that transparent accounting standards could have been an effective tool to do so. Moreover they recognize that uncoordinated deregulation can be harmful, and that the sequence of deregulation is also important. They support this view by highlighting that Japanese banks were not allowed to underwrite securities whilst the bond market was being liberalized, it was not until 1994 when banks were allowed to set up security subsidiaries, and this weakened banks (Kanaya and Woo, 2000).
It is therefore apparent that a number of potentially relevant lessons can be derived from Japan’s experience. Having critically analysed the literature, these core lessons are: action should be taken early (Amyx, 2004), policymakers must be flexible and willing to employ a broad range of measures to stabilize the financial system, including aggressive fiscal and monetary stimulus (Kang and Syed, 2009). Moreover, policy responses should be coordinated and attack the underlying problem of bad debt (Kobayashi, 2009), and finally, an exit strategy from the rescue policies must be carefully planned and implemented when signs of recovery emerge (Sheard, 2008).
I.IV Literature examining the applicability of these key lessons
It is not clear at this stage whether the lessons identified are applicable to the current, or even future, financial crises. To assess whether it is possible to successfully leverage these lessons to other financial crises many authors have compared Japan’s crisis with the current financial crisis. Such comparisons have revealed considerable differences, leading several authors to assert that the fundamentals of Japan’s crisis are too distinctive, limiting the applicability of Japan’s experience beyond the generic level.
Hoshi (2008) has pointed out that Japan’s problem was essentially nonperforming loans affecting the solvency of the commercial banking system. Conversely, in the US, the source of the crisis has been a housing market bubble involving subprime loans and mortgage-backed securities with very complex financial structures. Therefore, compared to Japan’s crisis, what is happening in the US is much more of a market liquidity problem, as it also is in Europe and the UK (Hoshi, 2008). Moreover, he highlights that in Japan stock prices peaked and collapsed just before real estate prices, while in the US the two happened almost simultaneously.
Similarly, Sheard (2008) has stressed that the reach of the current crisis is much greater than it was in Japan. Whereas Japan’s crisis was primarily a local phenomenon, the current crisis has had global consequences, since bad assets were securitized and spread throughout the global financial system. He concludes that the current crisis is a far more complex problem to address compared to the Japanese crisis, and this limits the applicability of lessons distilled from Japan. In this respect he adopts a similar view to that of Akio Makabe, an economics professor at Shinshu University, who remarks that “The Japanese policymakers of yesterday designed their bank resolution policies in a more stable macroeconomic and financial global setting” (JETRO, 2009, February Newsletter, p.3).
Furthermore, the view that the applicability of Japan’s lessons is limited is touched upon by Kobayashi (2008b) who notes that Japan’s problems were concentrated in about twenty financial institutions, where as the current crisis affects a large number of banks and many nonbank financial actors. Kobayashi also highlights that today public trust in the financial system and its agents is extremely low; a sharp contrast to Japan in the 1990’s.
However, analytical research on the comparative aspects of both crises also reveals striking similarities. For instance, the causes of the two crises are sufficiently similar. Cooper (2001) notes that the impulses driving the boom that preceded both crises can be traced to financial innovations and some form of financial liberalization, setting off a credit boom that fuelled rapid increases in asset prices, particularly house prices (Cooper, 2001). Moreover, he also points out that both booms were supported by lax monetary and fiscal policies and that in either case financial supervision and regulations were inadequate to prevent the emergence of large financial imbalances. Hoshi (2008) highlights the similarity that both Japan and the US experienced the unexpected failure of one of their largest financial institutions; Yamaichi Securities in Japan and Lehman Brothers in the US, which in both cases led to a spike in interbank loan rates.
Moreover, broader studies of the comparative aspects of financial crises indicate that financial crises are inherently similar. Of particular interest is a recent paper (Reinhart and Rogoff, 2008) which surveys a broad array of data to compare the scope and impact of the US subprime crisis with a number of previous financial crises, including the Japanese financial crisis. The paper asserts that the subprime crisis shares striking similarities with the financial crises that have preceded it, particularly in the run-up of asset prices, in debt accumulation, in growth patterns, and in current account deficits. The authors conclude that whilst the situation of the US is slightly different, in many ways, the mechanisms behind the crisis remain the same.
Hence, despite the idiosyncratic aspects, most economists believe that the Japanese model of bank resolution can serve as a source of guidance for countries facing financial crisis. Thus, Japan’s experiences can be seen to be relevant for other countries currently experiencing similar problems because they go to the heart of what a financial crisis is.
I.V Literature examining whether any of the lessons are being applied in the current financial crisis.
With the knowledge that lessons from Japan can be used as a form of guidance for countries facing financial crisis, the question arises; have countries dealing with the current financial crisis learned from Japan’s experience?
The economist Paul Sheard (2009) of Nomura Securities International, asserts that countries such as the US and UK are certainly behaving as if they have. He highlights the fact that in both countries, policymakers are acting aggressively on all fronts. “Fiscal, monetary, banking system and housing policy have all been mobilized to tackle the financial crisis, restore liquidity to financial markets, prevent deflation, and to end the recession” (East Asia Foundation Journal, Vol 4, No 1, Spring).
Moreover, Sheard (2009) suggests that the policymakers have learnt from Japan’s mistake of delayed intervention. Focusing on the US, he draws attention to the fact that it took just over one and a half years for the Government to put in place a large scale bank recapitalization framework (the Troubled Assets Relief Program), where as it took Japan roughly seven years to get to that point (Sheard, 2009). Similarly, he notes that by October 2008, the Federal Government had doubled the size of its balance sheet and engaged in a quantitative-easing strategy. In contrast, it took Japan over a decade to establish its quantitative-easing policy, and under it, the Bank of Japan only expanded the size of its balance sheet by about 35% and took about three years to do so (Sheard, 2009). This view is further supported by Tokyo based analyst Richard Jerram of Macquarie Securities who noted “the speed and aggression of the US response gives hope that it will avoid following the path of Japan in the 1990s” (JETRO, 2009, February Newsletter, p.3).
Furthermore, the view that the US has learnt from Japan’s experience is supported by the fact that Federal Chairman Ben Bernanke and Treasury Secretary Henry Paulson have explained that they formulated their responses to the current financial crisis after considering past crises (Faiola and Cho, 2008). In particular they looked at the US savings and loan episode of the 1980s and the bursting of Japan's economic bubble. From their analysis, they ultimately decided that the response to the current crisis needed to be a fast and substantial, two of the core lessons derived from Japan’s policy failures (Faiola and Cho, 2008). Furthermore, when the US Treasury planned the $700 billion bailout package (Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008) to address the financial crisis, it reportedly examined the experience of Japan from when it grappled with its banking crisis (Nanto, 2008). Moreover, as the US acts on the lessons obtained from Japan, so do other countries around the world follow suit (Kobayashi, 2009). The UK and many European countries have responded with similar vigour and aggression. Regarding the UK, Adam Posen (2009), a member of the monetary policy committee and Bank of England, highlights the speed and vigour with which monetary policy has responded in the wake of crisis.
Although US and European policymakers have responded to the ongoing crisis with much greater alacrity than did Japanese policymakers, at this stage it remains to be seen whether global policymakers have effectively attacked the underlying problem of bad debt (Kobayashi, 2009). Some analysts, such as Kobayashi (2009), feel that the US and Europe have failed to recognize one of the most important lessons from Japan’s experience; that market confidence can only be restored when progress is made on the painstaking process of disposing of nonperforming assets. He suggests that, whilst fiscal stimulus will help economies it will not resolve the crisis. He suggests that once the ‘painkilling’ effect wears off, US and European economies will plunge back into crisis. In this regard, US and European policymakers can be seen to be repeating the mistakes of Japanese policymakers, acting slowly to tackle the daunting task of solving nonperforming asset problems, clinging to wishful thinking by hoping that all of the current global economic problems will solve themselves in due time (Kobayashi, 2009).
Nevertheless, it is clear that global policymakers have taken onboard many of the lessons derived from Japan’s experience. Cementing the fact that the Japanese model of bank resolution has become a precedent for country’s formulating their own responses. However, literature detailing these issues has not yet had time to properly developed due to the contemporary nature of the current crisis.
Concluding Statements
In conclusion, academic research detailing the nature and causes of the Japanese crisis, as well as the policy responses implemented to resolve it, are well documented. However, there has been much less scholarly focus on extrapolating lessons from the crisis and very few authors have examined whether they are being applied to tackle the current financial crisis. Moreover, as the effects of the current crisis are still being digested, few authors have yet examined whether there is evidence of an improved response. This paper will attempt to go beyond the limits of existing literature by examining whether the lessons from Japan’s experience have been taken into consideration of governments addressing the current financial crisis. In this regard, this paper is intended to act as a basis for further discussions concerning effective crisis prevention and management to address potential financial disturbances.
Bibliography
Amyx, J. A., (2004), ‘The Japanese Financial Crisis: Institutional Rigidity and Reluctant Change, 2nd edition’, Princeton University Press
Aoki, M., (2000), ‘Information, Corporate Governance, and Institutional Diversity: Competitiveness in Japan, the USA, and the Transitional Economies’, Oxford University Press
Balázs, V., (2007), ‘Is Japanese Management Different: History and Future for Japanese Management Methods’, Corvinus University of Budapest paper, July
Bernanke, B. S., (2000), ‘Japanese Monetary Policy: A Case of Self-Induced Paralysis?’ in Ryoichi Mikitani and Adam S. Posen (eds.), ‘Japan’s Financial Crisis and its Parallels to U.S. Experience’, Special Report 13 (September 2000), Institute for International Economics.
Blanchard, O., (2000), ‘Bubbles, Liquidity Traps, and Monetary Policy’, in Ryoichi Mikitani and Adam S. Posen (eds.), ‘Japan’s Financial Crisis and its Parallels to U.S. Experience’, Special Report 13 (September 2000), Institute for International Economics.
Burkett, P., and Hart-Landsberg, M., (2003), ‘The Economic Crisis in Japan: Mainstream Perspectives and an Alternative View’, Routledge; Taylor and Francis group paper
Calder, K. E., (1993), ‘Strategic Capitalism: Private Business and Public Purposes in Japanese Industrial Finances’, Princeton University Press
Callen, T., and Ostry, J. D., (2003), ‘Japan’s Lost Decade: Policies for Economic Revival’, International Monetary Fund
Cooper, W. H., (2001), ‘Japan’s Economic Miracle: What Happened?’, Congressional Research Service Report: RL30176, October 1st
Fackler M., (2008), ‘Japan Offers a Possible Road Map for U.S. Economy’, New York Times, December 19th, http://www.nytimes.com/2008/12/20/business/worldbusiness/20yen.html
Faiola, A., and Cho, D., (2008), ‘Alternative Solutions Diverge From Administration's Approach’, Washington Post, September 24th, http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2008/09/23/AR2008092303695.html
Guillén, M. F., (2009), ‘The Global Economic & Financial Crisis: A Timeline’, the University of Pennsylvania paper
Hoshi, T., Sheard, P., and Woodford, M., (2008), ‘Lessons from the Japanese Bubble for the U.S.’, Columbia Business School, Symposium Summery Report, November 19th, http://ajadvisers.com/risingsunblog/wp-content/uploads/2009/02/cjeb-111908-report_lessons-from-the-japanese-bubble-for-the-us.pdf
Johnston, E., (2009), ‘Japan’s Bubble Economy: Lessons From When The Bubble Burst’, The Japan Times Online, January 6th, http://search.japantimes.co.jp/cgi-bin/nn20090106i1.html
Kamin, S. B., (1999), The Current International Financial Crisis: How Much is New?, International Finance Discussion Papers: No. 636
Kanaya, A., and Woo, D., (2000), ‘The Japanese Banking Crisis of the 1990s: Sources and Lessons’, IMF working paper: WP/00/7
Kang, K. , and Syed, M., (2009), ‘Overcoming the Global Financial Crisis: Some Lessons from Japan’s “Lost Decade”’, DICE Report, March, http://www.ifo.de/pls/guestci/download/CESifo%20DICE%20Report%202009/CESifo%20DICE%20Report%203/2009/dicereport309-forum3.pdf
Katz, R., (1998), ‘The System that Soared: The Rise and Fall of the Japanese Miracle’, M.E. Sharpe Inc
Katz, R., (2003), ‘Japanese Phoenix: The Long Road to Economic Revival’, M. E. Sharpe Inc., p. 278-283
Kobayashi, K., (2008a), ‘Financial Crisis Management: Lessons from Japan’s Failure’, VOX article, October 27th, http://www.voxeu.org/index.php?q=node/2483
Kobayashi, K., (2008b), ‘Subprime Loan Crisis: Lessons from Japan’s Decade of Deception’, Research Institute of Economy, Trade and Industry (RIETI), March
Kobayashi, K., (2009), ‘The G20's Blind Spot: President Obama Must Squarely Face the Bad Asset Problem’, VOX article, April 1st, http://www.voxeu.org/index.php?q=node/3385
Krugman, P., (1999), ‘It’s Baaack: Japan’s Slump and the Return of the Liquidity Trap’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity
Kunio, Y., (1979), ‘Japanese Economic Development: a Short Introduction’, Oxford University Press
Kuttner, K. N., and Posen, A.S., (2002), ‘Fiscal Policy Effectiveness in Japan’, Journal of the Japanese and International Economies, Volume 16, Issue 4, December 2002, p. 536–558.
Leigh, D., (2009), ‘Monetary Policy and the Lost Decade: Lessons from Japan’, IMF Working Paper: WP/09/232
Nakaso, H., (2001), ‘The Financial Crisis in Japan During the 1990s: How the Bank of Japan Responded and the Lessons Learnt’, Bank for International Settlements paper
Nanto, D. K., (2008),’ The U.S. Financial Crisis: Lessons From Japan’, CRS Report for Congress: RS22960
McCurry, J., 2008, ‘Japan's Lost Decade’, The Guardian, September 30th, http://www.guardian.co.uk/business/2008/sep/30/japan.japan
Pempel, T.J., (1998), ‘Regime Shift: Comparative Dynamics of the Japanese Political Economy’, Cornell University Press
Pempel, T.J., (1999), ‘The Politics of the Asian Economic Crisis’, Cornell University Press
Posen, A.S., (2004), ‘What Went Right in Japan?’, Institute for International Economics, policy brief
Posen, A. S., (2009), ‘Getting Credit Flowing: A Non-Monetarist Approach to Quantitative Easing’, Bank of England Publication, October 26th, http://www.bankofengland.co.uk/publications /speeches/2009/speech408.pdf
Reinhart, C. M., and Rogoff, K. S., (2008), ‘Is the 2007 U.S. Sub-Prime Financial Crisis So Different: An International Historical Comparison’, National Bureau of Economic Research Paper, February 5th
Saxonhouse, G. R., and Stern, R. M., (2002), ‘Japan’s Lost Decade: Origins, Consequences, and Prospects for Recovery’, University of Michigan paper: No. 485
Schaede, U., (1996), ‘The 1995 Financial Crisis in Japan’, the University of California: Working Paper 85, February
Schaefer, B. D., and Hwang, B. Y., (2002), ‘Addressing the Looming Financial Crisis in Japan’, the Heritage Foundation paper, March 26, http://www.heritage.org/Research/AsiaandthePacific/ BG1530.cfm
Sheard, P., (2009), ‘Japan and the Global Financial Crisis’, East Asia Foundation Journal, Vol 4, No 1, Spring, http://globalasia.org/articles/issue9/iss9_6.html
Vogel, S. K., (2006), ‘Japan Remodelled: How Governance and Industry are Reforming Japanese Capitalism’, Cornell University Press
Weiner, E., (2008), What the U.S. Can Learn from Japan's 'Lost Decade', NPR, http://www.npr.org/ templates /story/story.php?storyId=88156284&ps=rs
Woo-Cumings, M., (1999), ‘The Developmental State’, Cornell University Press
Wood, C. , (1992), ‘The Bubble Economy: the Japanese Economic Collapse’, The Atlantic Monthly Press
Wall Street Journal, September 19, 2007, in Keiichiro Kobayashi, 2008, Subprime Loan Crisis: Lessons from Japan’s Decade of Deception, Research Institute of Economy, Trade and Industry (RIETI), March
Lessons Learned and Advancing the US-Japan Relationship in Troubled Times, 2009, Japan External trade organization, focus newsletter, February, http://www.jetro.go.jp/en/reports/survey/pdf/ 2009_03_other.pdf
Pectus Excavatum
Monday, 25 April 2011
Thursday, 12 August 2010
Bankrupcy
If you have debt problems, you may be thinking about the possibility of bankruptcy; it isn't permanent, so you may choose it as a way of clearing your debts and making a fresh start. However, it's important to understand what bankruptcy is, you certainly shouldn't think of bankruptcy as being an easy way out because it certainly is not.
What is Bankruptcy?
Bankruptcy is a legally declared inability of an individual or business to pay its creditors, and can be a way of clearing debts that cannot be paid. It is possible for creditors to file a bankruptcy petition against a debtor (involuntary bankruptcy) in an effort to retain a portion of the debt which they are owed. However, in the majority of cases bankruptcy is initiated by the debtor (a voluntary bankruptcy). When an individual or business files for bankruptcy, all excess income and their non-essential assets, i.e. their property and possessions, are used to pay off creditors. At the end of the bankruptcy period, most of the debt is then discharged, allowing the debtors to make a fresh start; having shed the chains of debt, but at a significant cost.
Many people in modern society know people who have filed for or been affected by bankruptcy, it is becoming an increasingly common feature of today's borrow to buy culture. However, not many people completely understand the bankruptcy process, and hence are unable to deduce whether it is a good decision. If you are in a financially unstable position and are considering filing for bankruptcy yourself, or just looking to learn more about it, there are a few crucial points which you should be aware of.
Who is it Right for?
Bankruptcy is a serious matter; you'll have to give up your home and possessions of value. Whilst it gives you a fresh start, it is important to note that you will have to start from with nothing. Bankruptcy destroys your credit rating and as a result you will not be able to get a loan, any line of credit or financing for at least seven years. This is simply because creditors will be able to see that you have previously filed for bankruptcy and will refuse to enter into business with you.
However, you don't have to become bankrupt just because you're in debt. You can try to make arrangements with your creditors instead. For instance you can form an individual voluntary arrangement, where an insolvency practitioner helps you negotiate repayment terms. Many other repayment agreements exist and should be looked into before you make you final decision. To do this, it is often advisable to take the time to talk to a professional; they can take a look at your financial situation and determine the best course of action given your current situation and your debt levels. In some situations they may advise that you file for bankruptcy and will help you by providing you with detailed bankruptcy information.
What is Bankruptcy?
Bankruptcy is a legally declared inability of an individual or business to pay its creditors, and can be a way of clearing debts that cannot be paid. It is possible for creditors to file a bankruptcy petition against a debtor (involuntary bankruptcy) in an effort to retain a portion of the debt which they are owed. However, in the majority of cases bankruptcy is initiated by the debtor (a voluntary bankruptcy). When an individual or business files for bankruptcy, all excess income and their non-essential assets, i.e. their property and possessions, are used to pay off creditors. At the end of the bankruptcy period, most of the debt is then discharged, allowing the debtors to make a fresh start; having shed the chains of debt, but at a significant cost.
Many people in modern society know people who have filed for or been affected by bankruptcy, it is becoming an increasingly common feature of today's borrow to buy culture. However, not many people completely understand the bankruptcy process, and hence are unable to deduce whether it is a good decision. If you are in a financially unstable position and are considering filing for bankruptcy yourself, or just looking to learn more about it, there are a few crucial points which you should be aware of.
Who is it Right for?
Bankruptcy is a serious matter; you'll have to give up your home and possessions of value. Whilst it gives you a fresh start, it is important to note that you will have to start from with nothing. Bankruptcy destroys your credit rating and as a result you will not be able to get a loan, any line of credit or financing for at least seven years. This is simply because creditors will be able to see that you have previously filed for bankruptcy and will refuse to enter into business with you.
However, you don't have to become bankrupt just because you're in debt. You can try to make arrangements with your creditors instead. For instance you can form an individual voluntary arrangement, where an insolvency practitioner helps you negotiate repayment terms. Many other repayment agreements exist and should be looked into before you make you final decision. To do this, it is often advisable to take the time to talk to a professional; they can take a look at your financial situation and determine the best course of action given your current situation and your debt levels. In some situations they may advise that you file for bankruptcy and will help you by providing you with detailed bankruptcy information.
where to looki for bankruptcy information
The economy is constantly fluctuating in the world we live in, we all go through rough patches from time to time; an unforeseen emergency, you may lose your job, or possibly face a barrage of unexpected bills. If you end up falling behind on your debt payments and are unsure of how best to deal with the debt that seems to be mounting up, then you may want to consider filing for bankruptcy,. But before you file for bankruptcy it is important that you find out all you can about bankruptcy law information. However, this doesn't have to cost the earth; there are a number of places you can visit to get free bankruptcy information. This article will attempt to outline some of the best ways to get your hands on some free bankruptcy information.
The Library
The library is a great place to go to if you want to find free bankruptcy information. The library will offer you a range of resources from books on bankruptcy information to releases from the federal government. What’s more, the resources which you will find in the library are free. Even if a library does not have a certain book in its inventory, it will be able to order it from another library. Furthermore, library’s employ staff who will be willing to help you to find the best attainable free bankruptcy information.
The Internet
If you are looking for free bankruptcy information, the internet is a great place to turn too. On the World Wide Web, with just the click of a mouse, you can gain access to articles from experts and professionals about the bankruptcy process and how it will likely affect your finances. Moreover, it is not hard to find blogs and forums containing people who have themselves, filed for bankruptcy and will be able to provide you with their experiences and additional detail regarding bankruptcy information. The internet is therefore, definitely worth a look.
A Bankruptcy Lawyer
A lawyer can be a great resource for finding free bankruptcy information; it is not necessary to hire a lawyer, you just need to get in contact with them for a quick chat, and they will be able to tell you if filing for bankruptcy is the right choice. Talking to a law professional is a great way to obtain free bankruptcy information; hence if you are looking for free bankruptcy information, then you should call or email some of your local lawyers to see who will explain the process and the laws that will affect you.
The Library
The library is a great place to go to if you want to find free bankruptcy information. The library will offer you a range of resources from books on bankruptcy information to releases from the federal government. What’s more, the resources which you will find in the library are free. Even if a library does not have a certain book in its inventory, it will be able to order it from another library. Furthermore, library’s employ staff who will be willing to help you to find the best attainable free bankruptcy information.
The Internet
If you are looking for free bankruptcy information, the internet is a great place to turn too. On the World Wide Web, with just the click of a mouse, you can gain access to articles from experts and professionals about the bankruptcy process and how it will likely affect your finances. Moreover, it is not hard to find blogs and forums containing people who have themselves, filed for bankruptcy and will be able to provide you with their experiences and additional detail regarding bankruptcy information. The internet is therefore, definitely worth a look.
A Bankruptcy Lawyer
A lawyer can be a great resource for finding free bankruptcy information; it is not necessary to hire a lawyer, you just need to get in contact with them for a quick chat, and they will be able to tell you if filing for bankruptcy is the right choice. Talking to a law professional is a great way to obtain free bankruptcy information; hence if you are looking for free bankruptcy information, then you should call or email some of your local lawyers to see who will explain the process and the laws that will affect you.
Car Insurance for Young People/teens
If your son/daughter has just got their driving licence, the chances are that they will want to spend some time behind the wheel of your car as you worry over their safety and high auto insurance premiums. It is no secret that teenagers are far more likely to be involved in an accident than any other driver. This means premiums for young drivers are very high. This is why it is so important that you search around for cheap car insurance quotes, just as with any type of insurance; be it home insurance or life insurance. And you can start now with the useful advice listed in this article.
Firstly, you should add your teen driver up to your policy, instead of creating a seperate one. It may seem ridiculous to do so, since they will ramp up your insurance premium. However, it’s cheaper this way, since you will actually save money by signing up a new driver to your auto insurance policy. Also, to keep cost down even further, you and your teen should also do the following:
Practice safe driving. This applies to both you and your son/daughter. Your teen may be an inexperienced driver, but you are his ultimate role model. Therefore, you should be a living example to how to drive appropriately on the road. If both of you doing this together will help keep your auto insurance cost down even further.
Maintain good grades. Your teen may be going through school, and you want the best from him or her. And your auto insurance company does, also. Many companys offer a “good student” discount. It will lower your premium and might help your son/daughter to maintain good grades.
Buy an older/cheeper car. Older vehicles are less expensive, which is ideal for your teen to learn todrive. Any expensive vehicles should be driven by you, the experienced driver, since these actions will reduce premium costs.
Have your teen take driver’s education. This course will help teens drive better on the road, and auto insurance companies will give you and your teen a discount, if he or she passes.
Raise the deductible { voluntary excess ) on your policy. Your voluntary excess is what you pay when you claim, your insurer pays the rest. Your voluntary excess should be raised to lower your premium.
Remember to drop their coverage when your son/daughter goes to college. When your teen goes to college, most likely – unless they commute from home – they will not need to be on your auto insurance plan, if they plan on buying their own car insurance policy. No matter what though, teens must have a car insurance policy, since it’s against the law to drive without one.
Shop around for insurer's. Perhaps it’s time to switch insurers, if your current provider is giving you a high rate. It will allow you and your sibling to find a rate that’s fair and reasonable, especially if the new policy has a great coverage plan.
These tips will help reduce costs associated with young drivers. Be sure to also question your insurance agent about discounts or other cost-reducing strategies.
Firstly, you should add your teen driver up to your policy, instead of creating a seperate one. It may seem ridiculous to do so, since they will ramp up your insurance premium. However, it’s cheaper this way, since you will actually save money by signing up a new driver to your auto insurance policy. Also, to keep cost down even further, you and your teen should also do the following:
Practice safe driving. This applies to both you and your son/daughter. Your teen may be an inexperienced driver, but you are his ultimate role model. Therefore, you should be a living example to how to drive appropriately on the road. If both of you doing this together will help keep your auto insurance cost down even further.
Maintain good grades. Your teen may be going through school, and you want the best from him or her. And your auto insurance company does, also. Many companys offer a “good student” discount. It will lower your premium and might help your son/daughter to maintain good grades.
Buy an older/cheeper car. Older vehicles are less expensive, which is ideal for your teen to learn todrive. Any expensive vehicles should be driven by you, the experienced driver, since these actions will reduce premium costs.
Have your teen take driver’s education. This course will help teens drive better on the road, and auto insurance companies will give you and your teen a discount, if he or she passes.
Raise the deductible { voluntary excess ) on your policy. Your voluntary excess is what you pay when you claim, your insurer pays the rest. Your voluntary excess should be raised to lower your premium.
Remember to drop their coverage when your son/daughter goes to college. When your teen goes to college, most likely – unless they commute from home – they will not need to be on your auto insurance plan, if they plan on buying their own car insurance policy. No matter what though, teens must have a car insurance policy, since it’s against the law to drive without one.
Shop around for insurer's. Perhaps it’s time to switch insurers, if your current provider is giving you a high rate. It will allow you and your sibling to find a rate that’s fair and reasonable, especially if the new policy has a great coverage plan.
These tips will help reduce costs associated with young drivers. Be sure to also question your insurance agent about discounts or other cost-reducing strategies.
Sunday, 18 July 2010
The Clarke-Groves Mechanism: How to Induce Honesty (notes by Simon Vicary)
In the module so far we have established conditions for the efficient provision of a public good. We have also found one mechanism, the Lindahl model, which in important respects replicates the fundamental theorems of welfare economics for an economy with a public good. However, this mechanism is almost certainly too costly to operate as a practical proposition, and is in any case vulnerable to individuals misrepresenting their preferences in an attempt to lower the taxes they pay whilst at the same time still enjoying the public good that is provided by the taxes paid by others. We have also found that majority voting may under some circumstances deliver an efficient quantity of a public good, but it cannot be relied upon as a general rule. All this work raises a deeper and rather more difficult question:
Does there exist a mechanism which will guarantee Pareto optimality in all circumstances, and which will induce people to be honest when asked to reveal their preferences?
The reason why the second part of the question is needed is that it is assumed that the government is going to provide the public good. In doing this it needs to know the MRSGx schedules for each individual (that is, individual preferences). Hence individuals have to give the government some information about their preferences. If this information is false, then clearly the provision of the public good will not be optimal. As the motivation for misrepresentation is to lower one’s tax bill this problem of getting individuals to reveal their preferences is part of what is rather loosely referred to as the free rider problem. Put this way a partial reformulation of the question could be:
Can we find a general solution to the free rider problem?
In stating the free rider problem way back in 1955 Samuelson thought the answer to this question was “no”. He did not analyse the issue in any depth however, and economists rather left the things at that for the next 15 years. Little thought was given to how one might try to solve the free rider problem, until a number of articles starting with Clarke and Groves separately in 1971, seemed to suggest that it was in fact possible to solve the free rider problem. This work is the focus for this lecture. We shall find that the solutions provided by Clarke and Groves are only partial. Indeed the conclusion of the literature seems to be that there is in fact no general way round the free rider problem. I would like to emphasise this point at the outset as the most accessible paper for you, and one you should read (Tideman and Tullock (1976)), seems to suggest the contrary.
The reasons for these pessimistic conclusions will be revealed in the fullness of time. It may, though, be useful to start by clarifying in our minds the exact nature of the free rider problem itself.
1. Interpretations of the free rider problem
McMillan (1979) outlines three strands of the free rider problem. We have encountered all of them already in one way or another.
No Government: Full information on Utility
This is the world of Nash equilibrium that we looked at early on. Technically, as a game theorist would tell you, the basic model assumes that all agents have full information about everybody’s preferences. (Even more technically any individual’s preferences are common knowledge among individuals.) The key point though is that individuals act in isolation, deciding on how much they should contribute or donate to a public good. As we saw, contributions are typically too low, and the provision of the public good is sub-optimal. Everyone would be better off if each person contributed a bit more to the public good, but it is in no one’s interest to do this unilaterally. For a summation public good, individuals find themselves in a prisoner’s dilemma.
Here people take, or attempt to take, a free ride on the contributions of others. Put more precisely, an increase in total contributions by all other individuals in the community results in any one given individual lowering their own contribution. The reason for sub-optimality is that people think only of themselves. That is they decide on their contributions on the basis of costs and benefits to themselves alone. They do not take into account the fact that their contributions also benefit other consumers of the public good.
Government: No Information on Preferences
In a world of complete information the problem of government provision would be trivial. Therefore, to capture what is likely to be a benevolent government’s problem we assume the government does not know individuals’ preferences. It has in some way to rely on individuals telling the government what their preferences are. This could come about directly (through such things as opinion polls), or indirectly through observing the way people behave (for example inferring the value people place on the environment by looking at the extra amount they are willing to pay for such things as organically produced vegetables, for houses in traffic free areas etc. Once preferences have been found, the Samuelson condition (in principle!) can be applied to deliver what might be an efficient quantity of the public good.
As we saw with the Lindahl model, however, it seems individuals do not in fact have an incentive to reveal honestly their true preferences. Again, free riding is to blame. In this case, it appears people will want to under-state their preference for the public good so as to lower their tax bill. The crux of the problem lies in what seems at first glance like a very good idea: that tax payments should be related in some way to the benefit one receives from public expenditure. This seems to provide the source of the gain from free riding in this context. Any attempt to get round this problem would therefore have to penalise individuals for deviating from their (unknown) true preferences. As any misrepresentation is made to inflict some cost on the rest of the community, it might seem reasonable that any charge people pay for misrepresentation reflects the cost they impose on others.
As we shall see, this is the key idea Clarke and Groves exploited. But before we tackle this problem head on we need to fill in some background.
Large Numbers
McMillan also mentions the large number problem of Olson, as a third variant on the free rider problem (it gets worse as community size increases). This is slightly different from the other two, and will not concern us over much in what follows.
2. Second price auctions and how to induce honesty
The question of inducing honesty is not unique to the public goods problem. In fact there are a whole host of variants on this theme in economics, coming under the general heading of asymmetric information. After pioneering papers by Akerlof, Spence and Stiglitz (for which they got a Noble Prize), this became a very active area of research in the 1980’s, and indeed continues to be so. The classic and original paper in this area was by Vickrey in 1961, and it will be useful to start with a simplified version of a key argument in that paper. It concerns the first seemingly unrelated area of auctions.
Suppose you have a single item to sell. Often for unique single items the sale is by auction. However, there are many different types of auction. The classic method, probably the one that first comes to your mind, is what is often called the “English Auction”. Here individuals make ascending bids for the item. This is done openly. As the highest price bid rises, potential buyers drop out, and the “winner” is the last person to stay in the auction/bidding. He or she gains the object and pays the last price they bid. A second possibility would be to require potential buyers to submit a sealed bid. In this case potential buyers submit a bid to the auctioneer. This is not observed by other bidders. The object is sold to the highest bidder, and they pay the price they bid. This is referred to as a first price sealed bid auction. There are quite a few other possibilities.
Now a moment’s thought should convince you that in these auctions people will not bid honestly. The best way to see this is to think about the first price sealed bid auction. Suppose each individual has a maximum price they are willing to pay for the object. Will they write this maximum price on their submission to the auctioneer? Obviously not, because the maximum price is such that one is indifferent between: (a) not having the object and (b) having the object but paying this maximum price. There is therefore no possible way in which a person who submits their maximum price can gain from participating in the auction. Lowering the bid must result in some non-zero probability of positive gain, and is therefore to be preferred. Suppose, however, that you wanted to find out what people’s maximum willingness to pay is. How would you design the auction to do this?
Vickrey showed that the following auction (now sometimes known as a Vickrey Auction) would do the trick. Technically it is a Second Price Sealed Bid Auction. This works in the same way as a first price sealed bid auction, except that the winner (the person who submits the highest bid) pays the second highest price bid. It is not too difficult to see why this elicits honesty. I won’t go into details. Can you gain by raising your bid? Not if you have the highest valuation, and you might lose if this is not the case. What if you lower your bid? If you are not the person with the highest valuation you cannot gain, and you can only lose if you are that person. In short by submitting anything other than your true valuation you can never gain, and in some circumstances you will lose. Faced with a second price sealed bid auction honesty really is the best policy.
There are a number of observations to make about the second price auction which will be useful to bear in mind as we go through the Clarke-Groves mechanism.
(a) It might be thought that a second price auction is unsatisfactory from the point of view of the seller. This is misleading at best, and generally false. It turns out that all the auctions mentioned and many others produce the same expected revenue for the seller. This was shown by Vickrey, and his result has been generalised subsequently. The error in the statement lies in assuming that bidding is invariant with respect to the type of auction faced. This is obviously not true. The amount you might have to pay if you bid highest must have some impact on what you are prepared to bid.
(b) Things differ if we think of the seller as a bidder. The point is that the seller may have a reservation price for the article, and not be prepared to sell for less than this price. Suppose the rules of the auction allow the seller to set a reservation price? Will the seller set the reservation price honestly? The answer is in general no. By raising the reservation price in the range between the highest and second highest bids, the seller can increase revenue. It is possible therefore that he/she will want to put down a higher reservation price than his/her true valuation.
(c) Putting these two points together we see that we can get honesty from individuals in a group when the money raised goes outside the group. However, if the money stays within the group (as happens when we add the seller), general incentives to be honest do not seem to exist.
(d) How do we interpret the price paid by the winner? One way to look at it is as a compensating sum within the set of bidders. Suppose James has the highest bid and would win the auction if he participated. Suppose too that Mary is the second highest bidder and places a value of £20 on the object. If James participates he deprives Mary of the object. Put quaintly, he deprives the rest of the community of an article which it values at £20 (the object is a private good). So when James participates he pays a sum of money that would compensate the rest of the community (the set of bidders in this case) for his participation.
(e) However, following on from the last point, and in a way linking up with point (c) it is vital that although James pays a compensating sum, the compensation is not paid to anyone within the group. A moment’s thought again should convince you that as soon as compensation is actually paid the incentive to be honest collapses. Some one will have some sort of incentive to raise their bid in order to get hold of some of the compensating payments.
This may seem a rather contrived set of points to make, but together they provide a link to the question of how we can devise a mechanism that induces an honest revelation of preferences in a public good economy.
3. The Clarke-Groves Mechanism: Discrete Case
To see how the above principles can apply, let us take the simpler example of a discrete public good. Suppose we have a good that is either provided in one unit (G = 1) or not at all (G = 0). Examples might be a bridge, the restoration of a church tower, the saving of Private Eye etc. Suppose it costs £100 to deliver the good, and suppose there are three agents whose value placed on G is given in the table:
Table 1
Individual Valuations of the Public Good
Individuals Valuation Assigned Tax Net Benefit
A 40 35 5
B 70 35 35
C 20 30 -10
A Clarke-Groves scheme for this problem would work as follows:
(a) Each person is asked to submit their valuation of the public good (The valuations in the table are known only to the individuals themselves).
(b) The good is provided only if the sum of declared (there is no way of knowing for sure whether submitted valuations are true or not) valuations is as least equal to the cost of provision £100.
(c) If the good is to be provided, there are two parts to each individual’s (individualised) payment: (i) an assigned share; (ii) the compensating sum.
(d) The first part of any tax payment is an assigned share. The table gives the assigned numbers for our example. These assigned taxes are imposed. Individuals have no control over them. A natural assumption would be to assign them equally across individuals, but this is not necessary and not what we do in the table. Willingness to pay net of assigned taxes appears in the 4th column of the table.
(e) The compensating sum for each individual refers back to points (d) and (e) above. It is worked out by summing the willingness to pay for all other individuals in the community, and subtracting from this the total amount of assigned taxes they paid if the good is provided. Given that the good is to be provided we have to work out whether our individual’s participation in the community would make any difference to the outcome. If not, then no compensating sum is paid. If so then the imposed taxes are increased by the compensating sum in question.
(f) Given point (c) made about the second price sealed bid auction it follows that the money raised by the compensating sum should be thrown away. Or at least it should go outside the community.
Now apply this scheme to the example in Table 1. Table 2 takes the story on
Table 2
Working out the Compensating Sum
Individuals Sum Net Benefit n-1 Decision Compensation Paid
A 25 Y 0
B -5 N 5
C 40 Y 0
Suppose that our three individuals declare their preferences honestly. As the total sum of benefits exceeds £100, or as total net benefits exceed zero the good will be provided. Look now at individual A. Suppose A did not participate in the “vote” (you can imagine that A’s taxes are available to B and C). In this case the sum of net benefits over B and C results in 25 (= 35 – 10). This is positive, so A’s participation makes no difference to the community decision, and hence she pays no compensating sum. By repeating this procedure we find that B’s participation alters the decision the community makes. In fact B’s participation imposes a cost of 5 (= – (5 – 10)) on the community. Hence B must pay £5 as a compensating sum. C, as can easily be checked pays no compensating sum, which is just as well as she is made worse off by the provision of the good.
The final question about the mechanism is simply this. Does it indeed elicit an honest revelation of preferences? It can again be checked that by declaring a valuation different from the true one, individual cannot gain, and might lose. Note first that the compensating sum paid is beyond the individual’s control. An individual can only alter tax payments by altering the provision of the good. So A, for example, could lower her declared valuation. If she does this she pays no tax, but she also loses the benefit of the public good. As with the good provided she enjoys a net benefit of £5, she can only lose by doing this. Raising her declared valuation does not alter the tax paid, and therefore will make no difference to her welfare.
Given that the good is provided individual B pays a compensating sum of £5. His net gain from having the public good is 30 = 70 – 35 – 5. Lowering the valuation either has no effect on provision (with a constant compensating sum) or causes the good not to be provided, in which case he loses £30. Raising his declared valuation makes no difference to anything.
Finally consider C. C loses from the provision of the public good. As C’s valuation makes no difference to the decision, lowering the declared valuation makes no difference to the outcome, and no difference to her tax bill. Neither does raising her declared valuation.
It appears then that there is no way for any agent to do better than to make a truthful declaration to the authorities. Doing otherwise either has no impact on utility or it makes the individual worse off than he/she would otherwise be. Is this a quirk of the example, or does this property hold generally? It is of course a general property of this mechanism.
To prove that this mechanism really does induce honesty, note two relevant factors:
(a) The public good may or may not be provided. The condition for provision is: , or , where A is the cost of provision, and ci is individual i’s assigned tax should the good be provided.
(b) To find out whether an individual is pivotal, the inequality in (a) must be compared with the inequality . If the signs of the two inequalities are the same then the individual is not pivotal, and pays no compensation tax. If they do differ then the individual is pivotal in the sense that he/she changes the outcome as opposed to what the rest of community would decide.
There are four cases to examine, depending on whether the individual is pivotal or not and also whether the good is provided or not.
Case 1: G = 1, Pivotal Individual
First take the case of the good being provided, and the individual being pivotal. This is the case of individual B in the example. The individual in this case must make a compensating payment . By construction:
(ci is the assigned tax.) In this case we have:
with
Hence it must follow that (substitute the tax identity into the first inequality):
The left hand side is the return if the individual is honest. The right hand side represents the return when the declared valuation is so low as to mean the public good is not provided (and our individual ceases to be pivotal). This being so, it would never be in the individual’s interest to lower her declared valuation below the true value. To do so incurs the danger of losing the benefit . As tax payments are fixed either exogenously (ci) or by the declaration of other agents ( ), there is no prospect of gain. Naturally there is no gain to be had by increasing one’s declaration. We conclude that if you are pivotal, and the good is provided, you can only lose by doing anything other than declaring the truth.
Case 2: G = 1: Non-pivotal Individual
Now suppose the individual is not pivotal, but that the good is provided (this is the case of A and C in the example). In this case no compensating taxes are paid. If the public good is not provided then the following inequalities hold:
with
Raising declared valuation makes no difference to the outcome (the good is still provided) and no difference to taxes paid (the individual is still non-pivotal). Thus our individual’s utility is:
vi – ci
It might be possible for i to lower declared preferences so that the good is not produced. This could apply to C in the example who loses as a result of the good being produced. However, were i to succeed in this (actually it’s not possible for C in the example, but she doesn’t know this) then he/she becomes pivotal and has to make a compensating payment:
The only thing that happens now to i is that the compensating payment is made. The good is not provided, and no assigned taxes are paid. To find out whether it is worth lowering declared preferences therefore i must compare:
vi – ci with
But
Hence
The left hand side of the inequality is the individual’s utility when he/she is honest and the good is provided. The right hand side represents the return when preferences for the public good are under-stated, and it is not provided. Hence it follows that if our individual succeeds in causing the public good not to be produced then he/she is worse off. Our conclusion now is that if the good is going to be delivered then there is no way any one can gain by misrepresenting preferences, and there is always the possibility of making oneself worse off.
Case 3: G = 0 Pivotal Individual
The method used to show that honesty is the best policy is the same for when the good is not going to be produced. If the individual is pivotal she “stops” the good being produced when the rest of the community would want this to happen. The analysis uses the following two inequalities:
with
Lowering declared preference for the public good makes no difference to the outcome, but raising declared preference might cause the good to be produced. If so, then no compensating taxes are paid.
Compare the utility (utility with honesty) with vi – ci¬ (utility if overstatement succeeds in getting the good produced). By subtraction you should be able to convince yourself that:
vi – ci <
Our individual can only lose by overstating preferences for the public good.
Case 4: G = 0 Non-pivotal Individual
As with the last case lowering declared preferences makes no difference to the outcome, but raising preference could cause the good to be produced. In this case we use:
with
However, if the good is produced our individual becomes pivotal and pays a tax equal to:
The comparison is between utility when honest (0) and when overstatement succeeds in getting the good delivered. That is, between:
0 and
Hence yet again honesty is the best policy. Our final conclusion is that no matter what the circumstances, individual dishonesty at best makes no difference. Otherwise, it results in our individual being made worse off. In this way the Clarke-Groves mechanism ensures an honest revelation of individual preferences and in this way offers a final solution for the free rider problem.
4. The Clarke-Groves Mechanism: Continuous Case
Before examining some of the limitations of the Clarke-Groves scheme, we shall just note how it gets extended to a continuous public good. Actually relatively little changes, and there is no point in going into details. See Cornes and Sandler if you are interested. It is simply a matter of applying the principles already learnt.
Consider Figure 1. It is assumed that each individual has a quasi-linear utility function Ui = xi + vi(G), and, to keep things simple we assume a constant MRTGx = 1. The procedure works as follows:
(a) The government asks each individual to state their preference for the public good. In this context this means to write out their MRS schedule.
(b) Having gained each MRS schedule the government applies the Samuelson criterion by choosing the output at which the sum of the MRS equals the MRT.
(c) In determining each individual’s tax bill there are again two components: a pre-determined tax share over which the individual has no control, and a compensating sum, determined by the impact our individual’s statement of preferences has on the outcome.
(d) Once the level of G is determined individuals pay the tax. The pre-determined tax revenue is spent on providing the public good, and the revenue from the compensating payments is thrown away.
Let us see how this works out on the diagram. on the diagram represents our individual’s pre-determined tax share. Suppose people are honest.
(a) By equating the sum of declared MRS’s to the MRT the output of G is determined at 0Q.
(b) Now imagine that i does not participate in the process. The rest of the community would collectively, under this procedure decide on an output 0A, found by equating to the sum of their marginal tax rates (1 - MRTGx. This step corresponds to finding out whether the rest of the community would want a discrete public good given their (stated) preferences and costs.
(c) On the diagram our individual is pivotal in the sense that her participation raises provision from 0A to 0Q. As this is so, she must make a compensating payment.
(d) This compensating payment must equal, as before, the welfare loss suffer by the other n – 1 individuals in the community as a result of i’s participation.
(e) This aggregate loss is measured using standard welfare analysis (the area between the MC to the other individuals, 1 - and their aggregate marginal benefit schedule , area JKL).
(f) The line SS (synthetic supply) is draw such that area WXY is the same as JKL. It is a mirror image of the aggregate marginal benefit schedule for the other n – 1 agents.
(g) Thus the area JKL = WXY gives the compensating payment i must make in this case.
(h) The output chosen will always be such that the Samuelson condition is met.
This scheme produces honesty in just the same way as we saw earlier. To see this, consult Figure 2 where we reproduce the relevant part of Figure 1. Suppose our individual decides to over-state his preference for the public good. The provision rises from OQ to OQ1. The benefit of this rise to our individual is QYNQ1 whilst the cost is QYRQ1. Our individual loses by the area YRN. This area will always be positive for any overstatement of the MRS schedule. A similar conclusion can be reached by assuming our individual under-states preferences for the public good. This is left as an exercise.
The conclusion is that under the assumed conditions the Clarke-Groves mechanism induces individuals to report honestly their preferences for the public good.
Before dealing with some of the weaknesses of the mechanism, one point is worth making. In running through the analysis we found that it was always in the interest of our selected individual i to tell the truth. This analysis of course applies to all other individuals in the economy. However, we did not however enquire too deeply into what these other individuals were doing. Were they telling the truth about their preferences, or were they disguising their preferences in some way? Actually, it doesn’t matter. While we sort of assumed other people were revealing their preferences, the conclusion goes through if they are being dishonest. The reasoning we followed really dealt simply with what these other people had declared. If we were to assume a false set of declarations by the other people our reasoning would proceed exactly as originally, and we would find it still in our individual i’s interest to reveal preference truthfully. We conclude:
Regardless of what other people have done it is in the interest of each individual separately to reveal honestly their preferences for the public good.
In the language of game theory we would say: Truth telling is a dominant strategy in the Clarke-Groves mechanism.
Another pretentious way to say this is that the Clarke-Groves mechanism is Strongly Individual Incentive Compatible.
A natural question to ask is this: Do there exist other mechanisms with this property? It can be proved that the answer to this question is “no” Green and Laffont (1979). If we are interested in mechanisms that induce individuals to reveal their preferences for the public good under all circumstances, then we can restrict ourselves to Clarke-Groves mechanisms. It is useful to bear this in mind in what follows.
If the mechanism is so wonderful, why is it not used more often? Let us find out why.
5. The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem and its Implications
Our approach will be a little indirect, and requires us first to go back to the Arrow Theorem. Around about the time the Clarke-Groves mechanism was being developed (theoretically!) a remarkable theorem in the field of social choice was proved by Gibbard and Satterthwaite. It can be described as follows.
Suppose we have a community of n individuals, and suppose our community must choose between a number of alternatives S ={x1, x2,…….,xn}, where n ≥ 3. This problem is what Arrow originally had in mind. Suppose as with Arrow that the community has a mechanism for deciding which social state to choose given the declared preferences of the individuals. We can summarise this in the form of a function from the declared preference to the set of social states:
g: P→S x = g(P1, P2, ……,Pn)
where g is our function and Pi is the preference declared by individual i. g could be described as a social choice function. Voting, Lindahl and all the other procedures we have discussed so far would be classed as social choice functions.
We say a social choice function is manipulable at P = {P1, P2, ……,Pn} if there exists a false declaration of preference Pi* for some individual i such that:
g(P1, P2, …, Pi*,…,Pn) ≻i g(P1, P2, ……,Pn)
That is, individual i can make himself better off by making a false declaration of preferences. The work in our lecture up to now seems to suggest that the Clarke-Groves mechanism is non-manipulable, in that it is always in an individual’s interest to reveal preferences truthfully.
We would want any social choice function to have some desirable properties. Reflecting Arrow in some way, two can be stated:
Non-imposition
∀ x ∈ S, ∃ P such that x = g(P)
That is, take any social state. There must be some configuration of preferences that result in this social state being chosen. If you like, the constitution does not debar some alternatives. This, effectively, is Arrow’s unrestricted domain axiom.
Non-Dictatorship
∄ i such that x ∈ g(P) ⇔ x≻i y ∀ y ∈ S and for all preferences that could be stated by all individuals.
This is Arrow’s non-dictatorship axiom. There is no individual whose preference determines social choice regardless of the preferences of other people.
The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem
If the number of social states is greater or equal to three it is impossible to construct a social choice function that has the properties of non-dictatorship and non-imposition.
Put another way, if a vote is to be taken over more than two alternatives, then no matter how the voting system is designed it will be possible in some circumstances for somebody to gain by misrepresenting their preferences. You cannot eliminate strategic voting for any “sensible” voting system.
As well as its interest for actual voting systems, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem poses a problem. The Clarke-Groves mechanism involves many alternatives (this is even true of the binary choice problem we examined in detail given that one aspect of the problem was the tax people had to incur), it is clearly non-dictatorial, and has the non-imposition property. Yet we found that it is non-manipulable in the sense defined. There is clearly something funny going on here. Our next section finds out what this is.
6. Limitations of Clarke-Groves Mechanisms
How do we reconcile the Clarke-Groves mechanism with the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem? The answer lies in a half hidden assumption that was slipped in to the Clarke-Groves model.
No Income Effects
In explaining the Clarke-Groves mechanism for a continuous public good, as we did with Figure 1, we assumed utility to be quasi-linear. This ensures that the MRS functions never move around. It turns out that this assumption is quite vital to get the model to work. It is possible to extend the result so that truth telling is a dominant strategy with a wider class of utility functions. However, this cannot be done for general utility functions. (This is proved in Green and Laffont p 81). The reconciliation is therefore that the Clarke-Groves mechanism only “works” under a restrictive set of conditions. If you want to relate this point to earlier work, the assumption of quasi-linear utility violates the unrestricted domain assumption.
As an indication of the sort of theoretical trade offs involved, a parallel mechanism was devised in a heavily technical paper by Groves and Ledyard in 1977. This did work for general utility functions, but truth telling was only a Nash equilibrium strategy, not dominant strategy equilibrium. (How this would work in practice when people have to state preferences without knowing what other people’s preferences are is unclear). It seems therefore that some of the sharp properties of the Clarke-Groves model have to be sacrificed if it is to work for all utility functions. This general point is exactly what we would predict given the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem.
There are, however, other limitations
Clarke-Groves Mechanisms do not work for all public goods
Examples of this would where income distribution is a public good (either as a matter of social policy or as a question of deciding on the finance of a given project). Here there are individualised benefits from the public good, and individuals have an incentive to misrepresent preferences in order to gain them.
The Budget Constraint Problem
Even if we were to put these problems (as well as the cost of operating the system) aside there is still a serious problem with the Clarke-Groves mechanism. It is simple to state and easy to see. The mechanism does not in general produce a Pareto Optimum. The reason for this lies in the compensating sum that in general we must expect to have paid. The revenue gained in this must be thrown away, otherwise individuals will have an incentive to misrepresent their preference in order to gain this revenue.
By revenue, as this is microeconomics, we mean real goods and services. But if real goods and services are being disposed of then obviously the economy has not got to a true Pareto optimum. In a general sense, the explanation for what is happening here is reasonably straightforward. Valuable information is being hidden from the planners. In order to extract it some cost has to be incurred, and one way to think of this “budget surplus” is as a cost of extracting the information. This failure to reach full Pareto optimality is in fact a standard property of models with information asymmetry.
As an aside, if we look at Figure 1 we can see that there is one happy case where full Pareto optimality would be achieved. This is where the imposed individualised price of the public good implied by the tax sharing rule () corresponds with the Lindahl price. In this case, there is no budget surplus problem.
Vulnerability to Coalitions
Just note. The Clarke-Groves mechanism is invulnerable to individuals misrepresenting their preferences. It is not invulnerable to groups of individuals misrepresenting their preferences.
To conclude…
Recall that Clarke-Groves mechanisms are the only ones that guarantee that truth telling is always in the interest of the individual agent. If there is a “solution” to the free rider problem it is here. However, we have found that they “work” only for a restricted set of utility functions, they do not produce Pareto optimality and they are vulnerable to manipulation by coalitions of individuals. If these problems are serious then the conclusion we have to come to is that except in special cases the free rider problem of revelation of preference is insoluble.
Does there exist a mechanism which will guarantee Pareto optimality in all circumstances, and which will induce people to be honest when asked to reveal their preferences?
The reason why the second part of the question is needed is that it is assumed that the government is going to provide the public good. In doing this it needs to know the MRSGx schedules for each individual (that is, individual preferences). Hence individuals have to give the government some information about their preferences. If this information is false, then clearly the provision of the public good will not be optimal. As the motivation for misrepresentation is to lower one’s tax bill this problem of getting individuals to reveal their preferences is part of what is rather loosely referred to as the free rider problem. Put this way a partial reformulation of the question could be:
Can we find a general solution to the free rider problem?
In stating the free rider problem way back in 1955 Samuelson thought the answer to this question was “no”. He did not analyse the issue in any depth however, and economists rather left the things at that for the next 15 years. Little thought was given to how one might try to solve the free rider problem, until a number of articles starting with Clarke and Groves separately in 1971, seemed to suggest that it was in fact possible to solve the free rider problem. This work is the focus for this lecture. We shall find that the solutions provided by Clarke and Groves are only partial. Indeed the conclusion of the literature seems to be that there is in fact no general way round the free rider problem. I would like to emphasise this point at the outset as the most accessible paper for you, and one you should read (Tideman and Tullock (1976)), seems to suggest the contrary.
The reasons for these pessimistic conclusions will be revealed in the fullness of time. It may, though, be useful to start by clarifying in our minds the exact nature of the free rider problem itself.
1. Interpretations of the free rider problem
McMillan (1979) outlines three strands of the free rider problem. We have encountered all of them already in one way or another.
No Government: Full information on Utility
This is the world of Nash equilibrium that we looked at early on. Technically, as a game theorist would tell you, the basic model assumes that all agents have full information about everybody’s preferences. (Even more technically any individual’s preferences are common knowledge among individuals.) The key point though is that individuals act in isolation, deciding on how much they should contribute or donate to a public good. As we saw, contributions are typically too low, and the provision of the public good is sub-optimal. Everyone would be better off if each person contributed a bit more to the public good, but it is in no one’s interest to do this unilaterally. For a summation public good, individuals find themselves in a prisoner’s dilemma.
Here people take, or attempt to take, a free ride on the contributions of others. Put more precisely, an increase in total contributions by all other individuals in the community results in any one given individual lowering their own contribution. The reason for sub-optimality is that people think only of themselves. That is they decide on their contributions on the basis of costs and benefits to themselves alone. They do not take into account the fact that their contributions also benefit other consumers of the public good.
Government: No Information on Preferences
In a world of complete information the problem of government provision would be trivial. Therefore, to capture what is likely to be a benevolent government’s problem we assume the government does not know individuals’ preferences. It has in some way to rely on individuals telling the government what their preferences are. This could come about directly (through such things as opinion polls), or indirectly through observing the way people behave (for example inferring the value people place on the environment by looking at the extra amount they are willing to pay for such things as organically produced vegetables, for houses in traffic free areas etc. Once preferences have been found, the Samuelson condition (in principle!) can be applied to deliver what might be an efficient quantity of the public good.
As we saw with the Lindahl model, however, it seems individuals do not in fact have an incentive to reveal honestly their true preferences. Again, free riding is to blame. In this case, it appears people will want to under-state their preference for the public good so as to lower their tax bill. The crux of the problem lies in what seems at first glance like a very good idea: that tax payments should be related in some way to the benefit one receives from public expenditure. This seems to provide the source of the gain from free riding in this context. Any attempt to get round this problem would therefore have to penalise individuals for deviating from their (unknown) true preferences. As any misrepresentation is made to inflict some cost on the rest of the community, it might seem reasonable that any charge people pay for misrepresentation reflects the cost they impose on others.
As we shall see, this is the key idea Clarke and Groves exploited. But before we tackle this problem head on we need to fill in some background.
Large Numbers
McMillan also mentions the large number problem of Olson, as a third variant on the free rider problem (it gets worse as community size increases). This is slightly different from the other two, and will not concern us over much in what follows.
2. Second price auctions and how to induce honesty
The question of inducing honesty is not unique to the public goods problem. In fact there are a whole host of variants on this theme in economics, coming under the general heading of asymmetric information. After pioneering papers by Akerlof, Spence and Stiglitz (for which they got a Noble Prize), this became a very active area of research in the 1980’s, and indeed continues to be so. The classic and original paper in this area was by Vickrey in 1961, and it will be useful to start with a simplified version of a key argument in that paper. It concerns the first seemingly unrelated area of auctions.
Suppose you have a single item to sell. Often for unique single items the sale is by auction. However, there are many different types of auction. The classic method, probably the one that first comes to your mind, is what is often called the “English Auction”. Here individuals make ascending bids for the item. This is done openly. As the highest price bid rises, potential buyers drop out, and the “winner” is the last person to stay in the auction/bidding. He or she gains the object and pays the last price they bid. A second possibility would be to require potential buyers to submit a sealed bid. In this case potential buyers submit a bid to the auctioneer. This is not observed by other bidders. The object is sold to the highest bidder, and they pay the price they bid. This is referred to as a first price sealed bid auction. There are quite a few other possibilities.
Now a moment’s thought should convince you that in these auctions people will not bid honestly. The best way to see this is to think about the first price sealed bid auction. Suppose each individual has a maximum price they are willing to pay for the object. Will they write this maximum price on their submission to the auctioneer? Obviously not, because the maximum price is such that one is indifferent between: (a) not having the object and (b) having the object but paying this maximum price. There is therefore no possible way in which a person who submits their maximum price can gain from participating in the auction. Lowering the bid must result in some non-zero probability of positive gain, and is therefore to be preferred. Suppose, however, that you wanted to find out what people’s maximum willingness to pay is. How would you design the auction to do this?
Vickrey showed that the following auction (now sometimes known as a Vickrey Auction) would do the trick. Technically it is a Second Price Sealed Bid Auction. This works in the same way as a first price sealed bid auction, except that the winner (the person who submits the highest bid) pays the second highest price bid. It is not too difficult to see why this elicits honesty. I won’t go into details. Can you gain by raising your bid? Not if you have the highest valuation, and you might lose if this is not the case. What if you lower your bid? If you are not the person with the highest valuation you cannot gain, and you can only lose if you are that person. In short by submitting anything other than your true valuation you can never gain, and in some circumstances you will lose. Faced with a second price sealed bid auction honesty really is the best policy.
There are a number of observations to make about the second price auction which will be useful to bear in mind as we go through the Clarke-Groves mechanism.
(a) It might be thought that a second price auction is unsatisfactory from the point of view of the seller. This is misleading at best, and generally false. It turns out that all the auctions mentioned and many others produce the same expected revenue for the seller. This was shown by Vickrey, and his result has been generalised subsequently. The error in the statement lies in assuming that bidding is invariant with respect to the type of auction faced. This is obviously not true. The amount you might have to pay if you bid highest must have some impact on what you are prepared to bid.
(b) Things differ if we think of the seller as a bidder. The point is that the seller may have a reservation price for the article, and not be prepared to sell for less than this price. Suppose the rules of the auction allow the seller to set a reservation price? Will the seller set the reservation price honestly? The answer is in general no. By raising the reservation price in the range between the highest and second highest bids, the seller can increase revenue. It is possible therefore that he/she will want to put down a higher reservation price than his/her true valuation.
(c) Putting these two points together we see that we can get honesty from individuals in a group when the money raised goes outside the group. However, if the money stays within the group (as happens when we add the seller), general incentives to be honest do not seem to exist.
(d) How do we interpret the price paid by the winner? One way to look at it is as a compensating sum within the set of bidders. Suppose James has the highest bid and would win the auction if he participated. Suppose too that Mary is the second highest bidder and places a value of £20 on the object. If James participates he deprives Mary of the object. Put quaintly, he deprives the rest of the community of an article which it values at £20 (the object is a private good). So when James participates he pays a sum of money that would compensate the rest of the community (the set of bidders in this case) for his participation.
(e) However, following on from the last point, and in a way linking up with point (c) it is vital that although James pays a compensating sum, the compensation is not paid to anyone within the group. A moment’s thought again should convince you that as soon as compensation is actually paid the incentive to be honest collapses. Some one will have some sort of incentive to raise their bid in order to get hold of some of the compensating payments.
This may seem a rather contrived set of points to make, but together they provide a link to the question of how we can devise a mechanism that induces an honest revelation of preferences in a public good economy.
3. The Clarke-Groves Mechanism: Discrete Case
To see how the above principles can apply, let us take the simpler example of a discrete public good. Suppose we have a good that is either provided in one unit (G = 1) or not at all (G = 0). Examples might be a bridge, the restoration of a church tower, the saving of Private Eye etc. Suppose it costs £100 to deliver the good, and suppose there are three agents whose value placed on G is given in the table:
Table 1
Individual Valuations of the Public Good
Individuals Valuation Assigned Tax Net Benefit
A 40 35 5
B 70 35 35
C 20 30 -10
A Clarke-Groves scheme for this problem would work as follows:
(a) Each person is asked to submit their valuation of the public good (The valuations in the table are known only to the individuals themselves).
(b) The good is provided only if the sum of declared (there is no way of knowing for sure whether submitted valuations are true or not) valuations is as least equal to the cost of provision £100.
(c) If the good is to be provided, there are two parts to each individual’s (individualised) payment: (i) an assigned share; (ii) the compensating sum.
(d) The first part of any tax payment is an assigned share. The table gives the assigned numbers for our example. These assigned taxes are imposed. Individuals have no control over them. A natural assumption would be to assign them equally across individuals, but this is not necessary and not what we do in the table. Willingness to pay net of assigned taxes appears in the 4th column of the table.
(e) The compensating sum for each individual refers back to points (d) and (e) above. It is worked out by summing the willingness to pay for all other individuals in the community, and subtracting from this the total amount of assigned taxes they paid if the good is provided. Given that the good is to be provided we have to work out whether our individual’s participation in the community would make any difference to the outcome. If not, then no compensating sum is paid. If so then the imposed taxes are increased by the compensating sum in question.
(f) Given point (c) made about the second price sealed bid auction it follows that the money raised by the compensating sum should be thrown away. Or at least it should go outside the community.
Now apply this scheme to the example in Table 1. Table 2 takes the story on
Table 2
Working out the Compensating Sum
Individuals Sum Net Benefit n-1 Decision Compensation Paid
A 25 Y 0
B -5 N 5
C 40 Y 0
Suppose that our three individuals declare their preferences honestly. As the total sum of benefits exceeds £100, or as total net benefits exceed zero the good will be provided. Look now at individual A. Suppose A did not participate in the “vote” (you can imagine that A’s taxes are available to B and C). In this case the sum of net benefits over B and C results in 25 (= 35 – 10). This is positive, so A’s participation makes no difference to the community decision, and hence she pays no compensating sum. By repeating this procedure we find that B’s participation alters the decision the community makes. In fact B’s participation imposes a cost of 5 (= – (5 – 10)) on the community. Hence B must pay £5 as a compensating sum. C, as can easily be checked pays no compensating sum, which is just as well as she is made worse off by the provision of the good.
The final question about the mechanism is simply this. Does it indeed elicit an honest revelation of preferences? It can again be checked that by declaring a valuation different from the true one, individual cannot gain, and might lose. Note first that the compensating sum paid is beyond the individual’s control. An individual can only alter tax payments by altering the provision of the good. So A, for example, could lower her declared valuation. If she does this she pays no tax, but she also loses the benefit of the public good. As with the good provided she enjoys a net benefit of £5, she can only lose by doing this. Raising her declared valuation does not alter the tax paid, and therefore will make no difference to her welfare.
Given that the good is provided individual B pays a compensating sum of £5. His net gain from having the public good is 30 = 70 – 35 – 5. Lowering the valuation either has no effect on provision (with a constant compensating sum) or causes the good not to be provided, in which case he loses £30. Raising his declared valuation makes no difference to anything.
Finally consider C. C loses from the provision of the public good. As C’s valuation makes no difference to the decision, lowering the declared valuation makes no difference to the outcome, and no difference to her tax bill. Neither does raising her declared valuation.
It appears then that there is no way for any agent to do better than to make a truthful declaration to the authorities. Doing otherwise either has no impact on utility or it makes the individual worse off than he/she would otherwise be. Is this a quirk of the example, or does this property hold generally? It is of course a general property of this mechanism.
To prove that this mechanism really does induce honesty, note two relevant factors:
(a) The public good may or may not be provided. The condition for provision is: , or , where A is the cost of provision, and ci is individual i’s assigned tax should the good be provided.
(b) To find out whether an individual is pivotal, the inequality in (a) must be compared with the inequality . If the signs of the two inequalities are the same then the individual is not pivotal, and pays no compensation tax. If they do differ then the individual is pivotal in the sense that he/she changes the outcome as opposed to what the rest of community would decide.
There are four cases to examine, depending on whether the individual is pivotal or not and also whether the good is provided or not.
Case 1: G = 1, Pivotal Individual
First take the case of the good being provided, and the individual being pivotal. This is the case of individual B in the example. The individual in this case must make a compensating payment . By construction:
(ci is the assigned tax.) In this case we have:
with
Hence it must follow that (substitute the tax identity into the first inequality):
The left hand side is the return if the individual is honest. The right hand side represents the return when the declared valuation is so low as to mean the public good is not provided (and our individual ceases to be pivotal). This being so, it would never be in the individual’s interest to lower her declared valuation below the true value. To do so incurs the danger of losing the benefit . As tax payments are fixed either exogenously (ci) or by the declaration of other agents ( ), there is no prospect of gain. Naturally there is no gain to be had by increasing one’s declaration. We conclude that if you are pivotal, and the good is provided, you can only lose by doing anything other than declaring the truth.
Case 2: G = 1: Non-pivotal Individual
Now suppose the individual is not pivotal, but that the good is provided (this is the case of A and C in the example). In this case no compensating taxes are paid. If the public good is not provided then the following inequalities hold:
with
Raising declared valuation makes no difference to the outcome (the good is still provided) and no difference to taxes paid (the individual is still non-pivotal). Thus our individual’s utility is:
vi – ci
It might be possible for i to lower declared preferences so that the good is not produced. This could apply to C in the example who loses as a result of the good being produced. However, were i to succeed in this (actually it’s not possible for C in the example, but she doesn’t know this) then he/she becomes pivotal and has to make a compensating payment:
The only thing that happens now to i is that the compensating payment is made. The good is not provided, and no assigned taxes are paid. To find out whether it is worth lowering declared preferences therefore i must compare:
vi – ci with
But
Hence
The left hand side of the inequality is the individual’s utility when he/she is honest and the good is provided. The right hand side represents the return when preferences for the public good are under-stated, and it is not provided. Hence it follows that if our individual succeeds in causing the public good not to be produced then he/she is worse off. Our conclusion now is that if the good is going to be delivered then there is no way any one can gain by misrepresenting preferences, and there is always the possibility of making oneself worse off.
Case 3: G = 0 Pivotal Individual
The method used to show that honesty is the best policy is the same for when the good is not going to be produced. If the individual is pivotal she “stops” the good being produced when the rest of the community would want this to happen. The analysis uses the following two inequalities:
with
Lowering declared preference for the public good makes no difference to the outcome, but raising declared preference might cause the good to be produced. If so, then no compensating taxes are paid.
Compare the utility (utility with honesty) with vi – ci¬ (utility if overstatement succeeds in getting the good produced). By subtraction you should be able to convince yourself that:
vi – ci <
Our individual can only lose by overstating preferences for the public good.
Case 4: G = 0 Non-pivotal Individual
As with the last case lowering declared preferences makes no difference to the outcome, but raising preference could cause the good to be produced. In this case we use:
with
However, if the good is produced our individual becomes pivotal and pays a tax equal to:
The comparison is between utility when honest (0) and when overstatement succeeds in getting the good delivered. That is, between:
0 and
Hence yet again honesty is the best policy. Our final conclusion is that no matter what the circumstances, individual dishonesty at best makes no difference. Otherwise, it results in our individual being made worse off. In this way the Clarke-Groves mechanism ensures an honest revelation of individual preferences and in this way offers a final solution for the free rider problem.
4. The Clarke-Groves Mechanism: Continuous Case
Before examining some of the limitations of the Clarke-Groves scheme, we shall just note how it gets extended to a continuous public good. Actually relatively little changes, and there is no point in going into details. See Cornes and Sandler if you are interested. It is simply a matter of applying the principles already learnt.
Consider Figure 1. It is assumed that each individual has a quasi-linear utility function Ui = xi + vi(G), and, to keep things simple we assume a constant MRTGx = 1. The procedure works as follows:
(a) The government asks each individual to state their preference for the public good. In this context this means to write out their MRS schedule.
(b) Having gained each MRS schedule the government applies the Samuelson criterion by choosing the output at which the sum of the MRS equals the MRT.
(c) In determining each individual’s tax bill there are again two components: a pre-determined tax share over which the individual has no control, and a compensating sum, determined by the impact our individual’s statement of preferences has on the outcome.
(d) Once the level of G is determined individuals pay the tax. The pre-determined tax revenue is spent on providing the public good, and the revenue from the compensating payments is thrown away.
Let us see how this works out on the diagram. on the diagram represents our individual’s pre-determined tax share. Suppose people are honest.
(a) By equating the sum of declared MRS’s to the MRT the output of G is determined at 0Q.
(b) Now imagine that i does not participate in the process. The rest of the community would collectively, under this procedure decide on an output 0A, found by equating to the sum of their marginal tax rates (1 - MRTGx. This step corresponds to finding out whether the rest of the community would want a discrete public good given their (stated) preferences and costs.
(c) On the diagram our individual is pivotal in the sense that her participation raises provision from 0A to 0Q. As this is so, she must make a compensating payment.
(d) This compensating payment must equal, as before, the welfare loss suffer by the other n – 1 individuals in the community as a result of i’s participation.
(e) This aggregate loss is measured using standard welfare analysis (the area between the MC to the other individuals, 1 - and their aggregate marginal benefit schedule , area JKL).
(f) The line SS (synthetic supply) is draw such that area WXY is the same as JKL. It is a mirror image of the aggregate marginal benefit schedule for the other n – 1 agents.
(g) Thus the area JKL = WXY gives the compensating payment i must make in this case.
(h) The output chosen will always be such that the Samuelson condition is met.
This scheme produces honesty in just the same way as we saw earlier. To see this, consult Figure 2 where we reproduce the relevant part of Figure 1. Suppose our individual decides to over-state his preference for the public good. The provision rises from OQ to OQ1. The benefit of this rise to our individual is QYNQ1 whilst the cost is QYRQ1. Our individual loses by the area YRN. This area will always be positive for any overstatement of the MRS schedule. A similar conclusion can be reached by assuming our individual under-states preferences for the public good. This is left as an exercise.
The conclusion is that under the assumed conditions the Clarke-Groves mechanism induces individuals to report honestly their preferences for the public good.
Before dealing with some of the weaknesses of the mechanism, one point is worth making. In running through the analysis we found that it was always in the interest of our selected individual i to tell the truth. This analysis of course applies to all other individuals in the economy. However, we did not however enquire too deeply into what these other individuals were doing. Were they telling the truth about their preferences, or were they disguising their preferences in some way? Actually, it doesn’t matter. While we sort of assumed other people were revealing their preferences, the conclusion goes through if they are being dishonest. The reasoning we followed really dealt simply with what these other people had declared. If we were to assume a false set of declarations by the other people our reasoning would proceed exactly as originally, and we would find it still in our individual i’s interest to reveal preference truthfully. We conclude:
Regardless of what other people have done it is in the interest of each individual separately to reveal honestly their preferences for the public good.
In the language of game theory we would say: Truth telling is a dominant strategy in the Clarke-Groves mechanism.
Another pretentious way to say this is that the Clarke-Groves mechanism is Strongly Individual Incentive Compatible.
A natural question to ask is this: Do there exist other mechanisms with this property? It can be proved that the answer to this question is “no” Green and Laffont (1979). If we are interested in mechanisms that induce individuals to reveal their preferences for the public good under all circumstances, then we can restrict ourselves to Clarke-Groves mechanisms. It is useful to bear this in mind in what follows.
If the mechanism is so wonderful, why is it not used more often? Let us find out why.
5. The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem and its Implications
Our approach will be a little indirect, and requires us first to go back to the Arrow Theorem. Around about the time the Clarke-Groves mechanism was being developed (theoretically!) a remarkable theorem in the field of social choice was proved by Gibbard and Satterthwaite. It can be described as follows.
Suppose we have a community of n individuals, and suppose our community must choose between a number of alternatives S ={x1, x2,…….,xn}, where n ≥ 3. This problem is what Arrow originally had in mind. Suppose as with Arrow that the community has a mechanism for deciding which social state to choose given the declared preferences of the individuals. We can summarise this in the form of a function from the declared preference to the set of social states:
g: P→S x = g(P1, P2, ……,Pn)
where g is our function and Pi is the preference declared by individual i. g could be described as a social choice function. Voting, Lindahl and all the other procedures we have discussed so far would be classed as social choice functions.
We say a social choice function is manipulable at P = {P1, P2, ……,Pn} if there exists a false declaration of preference Pi* for some individual i such that:
g(P1, P2, …, Pi*,…,Pn) ≻i g(P1, P2, ……,Pn)
That is, individual i can make himself better off by making a false declaration of preferences. The work in our lecture up to now seems to suggest that the Clarke-Groves mechanism is non-manipulable, in that it is always in an individual’s interest to reveal preferences truthfully.
We would want any social choice function to have some desirable properties. Reflecting Arrow in some way, two can be stated:
Non-imposition
∀ x ∈ S, ∃ P such that x = g(P)
That is, take any social state. There must be some configuration of preferences that result in this social state being chosen. If you like, the constitution does not debar some alternatives. This, effectively, is Arrow’s unrestricted domain axiom.
Non-Dictatorship
∄ i such that x ∈ g(P) ⇔ x≻i y ∀ y ∈ S and for all preferences that could be stated by all individuals.
This is Arrow’s non-dictatorship axiom. There is no individual whose preference determines social choice regardless of the preferences of other people.
The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem
If the number of social states is greater or equal to three it is impossible to construct a social choice function that has the properties of non-dictatorship and non-imposition.
Put another way, if a vote is to be taken over more than two alternatives, then no matter how the voting system is designed it will be possible in some circumstances for somebody to gain by misrepresenting their preferences. You cannot eliminate strategic voting for any “sensible” voting system.
As well as its interest for actual voting systems, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem poses a problem. The Clarke-Groves mechanism involves many alternatives (this is even true of the binary choice problem we examined in detail given that one aspect of the problem was the tax people had to incur), it is clearly non-dictatorial, and has the non-imposition property. Yet we found that it is non-manipulable in the sense defined. There is clearly something funny going on here. Our next section finds out what this is.
6. Limitations of Clarke-Groves Mechanisms
How do we reconcile the Clarke-Groves mechanism with the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem? The answer lies in a half hidden assumption that was slipped in to the Clarke-Groves model.
No Income Effects
In explaining the Clarke-Groves mechanism for a continuous public good, as we did with Figure 1, we assumed utility to be quasi-linear. This ensures that the MRS functions never move around. It turns out that this assumption is quite vital to get the model to work. It is possible to extend the result so that truth telling is a dominant strategy with a wider class of utility functions. However, this cannot be done for general utility functions. (This is proved in Green and Laffont p 81). The reconciliation is therefore that the Clarke-Groves mechanism only “works” under a restrictive set of conditions. If you want to relate this point to earlier work, the assumption of quasi-linear utility violates the unrestricted domain assumption.
As an indication of the sort of theoretical trade offs involved, a parallel mechanism was devised in a heavily technical paper by Groves and Ledyard in 1977. This did work for general utility functions, but truth telling was only a Nash equilibrium strategy, not dominant strategy equilibrium. (How this would work in practice when people have to state preferences without knowing what other people’s preferences are is unclear). It seems therefore that some of the sharp properties of the Clarke-Groves model have to be sacrificed if it is to work for all utility functions. This general point is exactly what we would predict given the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem.
There are, however, other limitations
Clarke-Groves Mechanisms do not work for all public goods
Examples of this would where income distribution is a public good (either as a matter of social policy or as a question of deciding on the finance of a given project). Here there are individualised benefits from the public good, and individuals have an incentive to misrepresent preferences in order to gain them.
The Budget Constraint Problem
Even if we were to put these problems (as well as the cost of operating the system) aside there is still a serious problem with the Clarke-Groves mechanism. It is simple to state and easy to see. The mechanism does not in general produce a Pareto Optimum. The reason for this lies in the compensating sum that in general we must expect to have paid. The revenue gained in this must be thrown away, otherwise individuals will have an incentive to misrepresent their preference in order to gain this revenue.
By revenue, as this is microeconomics, we mean real goods and services. But if real goods and services are being disposed of then obviously the economy has not got to a true Pareto optimum. In a general sense, the explanation for what is happening here is reasonably straightforward. Valuable information is being hidden from the planners. In order to extract it some cost has to be incurred, and one way to think of this “budget surplus” is as a cost of extracting the information. This failure to reach full Pareto optimality is in fact a standard property of models with information asymmetry.
As an aside, if we look at Figure 1 we can see that there is one happy case where full Pareto optimality would be achieved. This is where the imposed individualised price of the public good implied by the tax sharing rule () corresponds with the Lindahl price. In this case, there is no budget surplus problem.
Vulnerability to Coalitions
Just note. The Clarke-Groves mechanism is invulnerable to individuals misrepresenting their preferences. It is not invulnerable to groups of individuals misrepresenting their preferences.
To conclude…
Recall that Clarke-Groves mechanisms are the only ones that guarantee that truth telling is always in the interest of the individual agent. If there is a “solution” to the free rider problem it is here. However, we have found that they “work” only for a restricted set of utility functions, they do not produce Pareto optimality and they are vulnerable to manipulation by coalitions of individuals. If these problems are serious then the conclusion we have to come to is that except in special cases the free rider problem of revelation of preference is insoluble.
The Lindahl Model (notes by Simon Vicary)
1. The Story so Far
Our last lecture found out that voluntary action (the market mechanism) was likely to bring about a sub-optimal provision of the public good, as a result of individuals trying to take a free ride on the contributions of others. One obvious solution to this inefficiency is to recommend some form of government intervention. Indeed many of the services provided by governments have strong public good characteristics, and these are also important in areas in which the government intervenes rather than provides (e.g. environmental regulation). Defence, as we have seen, in many respects gets close to a pure public good, and the same can be said about “law and order”. The issue is rather more blurred with areas like education and health, but even so there are certainly some public good elements to what the government provides.
However, government provision of a public good raises a whole series of new questions. In fact it is a massive area of enquiry in its own right, in some respects incorporating political science. In this module we cannot hope here to do anything other than provide some basic ideas. The traditional starting point for economists in thinking about the public sector and in particular public expenditure is the Lindahl Model. In some ways this is a rather elusive concept, as it can be looked at in a variety of different ways:
• An alternative way of representing the Samuelson analysis
• A positive theory about how government expenditure decisions are arrived at
• A normative theory about how government expenditure should be arrived at
• An analytical device for judging alternative mechanisms by which government expenditure decisions are arrived at (somewhat similar to perfect competition in a world of private goods)
2. The Benefit Approach to Taxation
Modern public economics grew out of the old sub-discipline of public finance. A key issue in this older tradition concerned the concerned the basis of what could be called a fair tax. There were two approaches:
• The Benefit Approach. Here a fair tax was based the benefit an individual received from government expenditure. People who benefited more from public expenditure would, according to this school, have to incur a higher tax bill. This line of approach was particularly popular with continental economists, especially Italians and Scandinavians, although British thinkers adopted it in the 18th century stemming from a social contract view of the state.
• The Ability to Pay Approach. Here a just tax was based on an individual’s ability to pay. Those with a higher ability to pay should pay more taxes than those with a lower ability. This school of though was more popular in Anglo-Saxon countries, especially in the later 19th century possibly because of the stronger influence of utilitarian thinking.
Modern welfare economics has rather dispensed with debates of this kind, but both lines of thought have left their mark. The key idea of the benefit approach was that taxes should represent a payment for services delivered. The relationship of the government to the citizen was therefore one not in principle different from that between individuals in the community involved in mutually beneficial exchange. The state as such is only justified to the extent to which it provides benefits to individual citizens. The mainline value judgements adopted by modern welfare economics are Paretian, and the question of ultimate “justice” is not pursued any further than this. Taxes in the modern view are desirable if they lead to Pareto efficiency (subject to any distributive objectives about which Paretianism itself remains silent).
The benefit idea was revived by the Swedish economist Knut Wicksell in 1896, and in the hands of his pupil Lindahl, together with later developments led to a re-run of the Fundamental Theorems of welfare economics when public goods are present. Wicksell started from the following presumptions:
• People should not be coerced into paying for goods or services they do not want
• Public goods are more efficiently provided by the group as a whole, so individuals need to communicate their preferences to others
• To ensure that no coercion takes place, the appropriate principle a government must make in determining its expenditure-tax decisions is unanimity.
Although Wicksell wrote before the Paretian approach got established as the mainline form of welfare economics, his thinking fits very neatly into this approach. In a way, it represents an extreme form of Paretianism. When there are collective decisions to be made, how do we guarantee that no one is going to be made worse off? Unanimity (or giving each person a veto) would seem to be the only way. Wicksell realised, of course, that unanimity would be difficult in practice, but it was a principle to aim for, and in making decisions there should be “approximate unanimity”. The difficulties can be seen if we take another two person economy, and suppose individuals are bargaining over tax bills and provision of the public good. On Figure 1 we illustrate.
The area ABCD represents the area of Pareto improvement over the initial position without government. To see this note that the horizontal axis represents the provision of the public good, and the vertical individual A’s share of the total cost of whatever provision is decided upon. The indifference curve going through the origin represents the utility A receives in a state of anarchy (no government) (no taxes no government expenditure). With a veto over any decision A can be sure of never getting a utility level below this. The indifference curve going through the point (0, 1) fulfils a similar function for individual B.
The “model” of public expenditure determination goes as follows. The government announces a tax-expenditure package, say, point F. If both agents are better off than their initial position then they vote to accept this package, and point F is the next starting point. If the proposed package lies outside ABCD then at least one person will veto it, and it will be rejected. The government then produces another package. Starting from F another area of Pareto improvement can be traced out by the indifference curves going through F, and the government reformulates another package in the hope of finding another Pareto improvement. Once such a package has been found to which no one objects (vetoes) then this becomes the new starting point, and the process starts again. Equilibrium is finally reached when a package has been found for which for any counter proposal made there is always an objector. Such a point will be found somewhere on the set of Pareto optima, the dashed line (locus of tangencies) on Figure 1. It is not too difficult to show that tangency of the indifference curves on Figure is equivalent to the fulfilment of the Samuelson condition for Pareto optimality.
This, in simple terms is how the Wicksell model of ideal public expenditure should go. No one would argue for this to taken literally, but in a curious way it is quite instructive:
• Taken literally it is a process that guarantees Pareto optimality. However, its very artificiality may suggest that there are serious difficulties in the way of achieving this in practice.
• If each iteration is costly, as we would expect, then this would be a very expensive way of determining public expenditure
• Although stylised, the model picks up an important aspect of politics in modern democratic states. The determination of public expenditure is a major issue, as is the related determination of the tax burden. The process of determining these variables is accompanied by a lot of bargaining, both within and between government departments, and also, significantly, by lobbying by private interests
• Although Wicksell’s model is in a way within the benefit tradition, in one respect he is quite modern. He was careful to point out that his scheme was valid only once the question of the optimum distribution of income had been settled. Hence he separates out allocation and distributional questions in very much the same way as the fundamental theorems aim to do
• There is an obvious problem with the model even on its own terms. Why should people be honest in responding to successive government packages? Why pretend not to want the public good in an attempt to lower one’s own tax bill? This is a problem to which we shall return
• The final package (t, G) is indeterminate. We could end up anywhere on the line BD. There is no obvious way within the limits of the model to say where this might be. Incidentally, this point shows too that Wicksell’s point about income distribution has not been fully settled: the actual way this process proceeds could have quite significant implications for the distribution of welfare between individuals.
The Buchanan-Tullock Optimal Constitution
Wicksell’s idea proved quite influential, and, as is the way with these things, it developed in a number of differing ways. One such was the “optimal constitution” approach developed by Buchanan and Tullock in their 1962 book The Calculus of Consent. A central part of this book was an optimal voting scheme justified by unanimity. The idea was that while it would be too costly to rely on unanimity to reach every single tax-expenditure made by governments, the principle of unanimity could be preserved if everyone gave their consent to the process by which such decisions were made.
It is worth digressing a little to see this development of Wicksell’s idea. Buchanan and Tullock’s approach can be characterised in two ways:
• Like, Wicksell, they took Paretian value judgements seriously
• They consciously adopted a view of the state that revived the social contract tradition that originated in England in the 17th century.
The practical counterpart of their theory was the formation of the constitution of the United States in 1789.
Starting from Wicksell’s thinking they took it that Paretian value judgements should be treated seriously. No one should be coerced into submitting to laws or, for our purposes here, having to pay taxes without their consent. If we start from this point then in principle each person should have a veto over any law proposed, or any proposal to raise taxes, as with Wicksell. However, the cost of doing this is likely to be prohibitive, and probably going to satisfy no one. One country which did use the veto in its parliament (sejm) was Poland in the 17th and 18th centuries. This was hardly a good example of unanimity in action. The veto (liberum veto) was abolished in 1791 just four years before the country disappeared in a (final) partition between Austria, Prussia and Russia.
See Wikipedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sejm for some details.
Wishing for unanimity as a principle to underlie collective decisions, but recognising that it was impractical to have unanimity in every decision that has to be made, Buchanan and Tullock shifted the principle back one stage. People give their consent to each collective decision not if they approve of the decision itself, but if they have given their consent to the manner in which it was made. That is, everybody gives their consent to the “constitution”. This, as we have already seen, is to be thought of as the procedure by which this actual decisions (here most relevantly on taxation) are made. The picture they have is therefore quite parallel to the formation of the constitution of the USA, and, as a more recent possible example, to the establishment of democracy in the Eastern Europe.
This idea, though, raises the question of what sort of constitution would emerge from unanimous consent. Not much is said about the legal details in their book, but the principle by which decisions should be made is set out in the central chapter of the book, and illustrate on Figure 2 Here we have two cost functions. The decision-making function represents the cost of making a decision as determined by the percentage of individuals whose consent would be required. Quite possibly this becomes infinite as this approaches unanimity. The second function, the so-called “external cost” represents the possibility of lost of benefits from not being able to achieve Pareto optimality, or perhaps the expected cost of have a decision that makes the individual worse off. However we look at it, unanimity guarantees that no one will be made worse off or exploited by others, and it is reasonable to assume that this is downward sloping. Total cost is simply the sum of these two. So our individual would want a constitution that required the degree of consent given on the horizontal axis, the “optimal constitution”.
Various points can be made about this piece of analysis:
• If we think in terms of voting rules, the “optimal constitution” point could well vary as between the degree of consent required for different types of measure. It is notable, for example, that often a higher percentage of a vote is required for constitutional amendments.
• The schedules in Buchanan are not well defined. It is not clear what they mean in other than a very general sense.
• There is no reason why “majority rule” should have any special status as a voting scheme under this approach. This is argued by Buchanan and Tullock themselves, although they may overplay their hand because……..
• Voting rules that require more than 50% consent are not reversible. That it, they cannot be overturned by another coalition of voters. It 40% approve of a measure, then 40% could also vote to have it reversed. It is possible therefore that even though the schedules are ill-defined they have not been drawn accurately. There may be a jump in the decision-making function at 50%.
• In one sense Buchanan and Tullock do not solve the problem they pose. If our diagram represents what one individual thinks, there is no reason why the “optimal constitution” will not differ for another individual. It is not clear what happens at this point.
• One can regard the Buchanan-Tullock optimal constitution as an attempt to escape the dilemma of the Arrow Theorem. Unanimity might be easier to achieve for a constitution than for actual day-to-day decisions. However, there is no guarantee of this within the framework B-T develop.
• Buchanan and Tullock compound this last problem by asserting that at the constitutional stage people have already established a set of property rights. They negotiate about the constitution on this basis. This makes the possibility of unanimity less likely. To take the US example, an unpleasant one, it is reasonable to suppose that slaves in the 18th century USA would, had they been asked, have expressed rather different views about the constitution from the slave owners who were instrumental in writing the constitution.
• One can interpret Rawls’ 1971 A Theory of Justice as a way of clearing up this obscurity in B-T. His view was that a constitution should be based on what individuals would agree to behind a veil of ignorance. That is, people would know how society would be run, what laws and rules it would have, but would not know their identity within that society. They would have an equal chance of being any “named” individual. So they could be a slave owner, if it were a case of joining 18th century USA, but it would be much more likely that to be a slave. Who would consent to slavery in this case? Behind the veil of ignorance, it becomes more plausible that unanimity could be achieved. We could therefore interpret Rawls as trying to find a way round the Arrow problem
Another approach which leads into modern general equilibrium theory was initiated by Wicksell’s fellow Swede Erik Lindahl. To this we now turn.
3. The Lindahl Model: Two Person Economy
Lindahl’s work published in 1919 refined that of Wicksell. We can get an idea of the key points by looking again at the Wicksell diagram. Consider Figure 3. The indifference map is reproduced as in Figure 1, but now individuals are asked a different question. Instead of “Do you approve this total tax-expenditure package?” they are asked, “If you had to pay x% of the tax bill what quantity of the public good would you want to see provided?” Although the fundamental features of the Wicksell approach are preserved, there are one or two significant differences in the way we can look at the model. The key difference is that after setting personal tax rates the government/planners look at the responses individual make. If people are unanimous then the process stops and the tax rates and provision of the public good are determined accordingly. If people are not unanimous, then the government adjusts tax rates and puts the question again to the electorate. A natural procedure would be to raise the tax rates for those who want a high provision of the public good, and lower the tax rate for those who want low provision. The process continues until people are unanimous.
To see how this might work out, first imagine we alter the share of tax that individual A must pay, and trace out her responses. This we do on Figure 3. Clearly, as the tax share falls in some sense the price of the public good to our individual must also fall. Hence by tracing out the locus of tangencies as we do we must derive some sort of a demand curve for the public good. We can repeat this procedure for individual B. As lowering tA means tB = 1 – tA must rise the demand curve we draw will be upward sloping. The result is shown on Figure 4. Naturally something significant must be happening at the point at which the two demand curves intersect. This point indeed represents the (unique) Lindahl equilibrium on the diagram where people are unanimous about how much of the public good should be provided. Various comments follow…
• The significance of the intersection is that again as with Wicksell individuals are unanimous about the tax expenditure package. However, in this case the unanimity takes a slightly different form. Given the tax shares no one wants to alter the quantity of the public good. If you could imagine this in a political system, this could be interpreted as meaning that no one would want to lobby to alter the level of government expenditure.
• This last point can be illustrated by drawing in the indifference curves for point L, the Lindahl equilibrium on Figure 4. Given the way the demand curves were constructed, not only will we have tangency but the each indifference curve will be horizontal at this point. Given the tax share, each person consumes exactly the quantity of the public good they would want to consume. With Wicksell it is possible to have an equilibrium in which one person would want more G given their tax share, and their partner less (Draw a diagram to confirm this point).
• Suppose, to keep life simple, we have a constant cost economy, so the public good price, pG, is fixed. If the tax share for individual is tA then the expression tApG represents the effective price of the public good for individual A. A similar point applies to B. (The assumption of constant cost is not essential to this argument. These personalised prices can simply be defined in the same way for a variable cost economy. In this case it might perhaps be better to refer to t as the cost share rather than the share of the tax bill).
• The “personalised prices” are referred to a Lindahl Prices. Usually the writer uses this term to refer to the equilibrium prices, but this semantic issue is not important. The key point is that with (equilibrium) Lindahl prices individuals get exactly the quantity of the public good that they would choose if they had to pay their Lindahl price. In practice, of course, people cannot choose the quantity of a public good in the same way as they do the quantity of a private good. However, the Lindahl model produces an outcome in which things are no different from what they would be if individuals had this choice.
• This last point means that there is a sense in which the Lindahl model converts a public good economy to one which is analytically equivalent to a private good economy.
This being the case, a natural question to ask is whether the Lindahl model has the equivalent of the two Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics. That is, is it the case that all Lindahl equilibria are Pareto optimal? And is it also true that any specified Pareto optimum can be realised as a Lindahl equilibrium? Not only do the last couple of points suggest the questions, they also suggest a way of answering them. For if a notional equivalence between a Lindahl economy and a private goods economy can be established then the proofs of the original fundamental theorems can be used to shown that the Lindahl model is the public goods analogue of the competitive mechanism for a private goods economy.
4. The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics Revisited
It is easy to show that at any Lindahl equilibrium the Samuelson condition must hold:
Given the replication property referred to in the last section, at any Lindahl equilibrium, and given any individual i, with a private good x and a public good G, the following condition must hold:
pG is the actual price paid for delivery of the public good. We assume that the public good is produced by competitive firms. Hence:
Now sum this equation over all n individuals:
This is the Samuelson condition.
Technically, however, this does not provide us with a proof of the first Fundamental condition. The Samuelson condition is a necessary, not a sufficient, condition for a Pareto optimum. However, this argument suggests, correctly, that in all standard cases the analogue of the first theorem holds. In fact under pretty much the same conditions as with a private good economy we have:
Theorem 1
Any Lindahl Equilibrium is Pareto Optimal.
The second theorem is a bit more difficult, but in its technical details the proof goes through in pretty much the same way as the original theorem. The key technical assumption is again convexity, which is needed to ensure the existence of a set of (Lindahl) prices. Once these have been found, then utility and profit maximisation do the rest of the work. We can show the second theorem diagrammatically using the diagram developed by Cornes and Sandler, Figure 5.
The dotted line in this diagram is a 45o line, and the line AC is the set of Pareto Optima. Our problem is this. Can we specify any point on AC, and then (at least in principle) achieve this point as a Lindahl equilibrium?
Assuming constant cost, a Lindahl set of prices for this economy would be shown as a straight line going through the origin. (Individuals pay a fixed share of whatever it is that is delivered). Suppose we are interested in reaching point A. As the diagram shows, the tangent going through point A does not go through the origin. Hence if we are to reach point A some prior redistribution must occur. To see how this happens on the diagram, recall the Warr Neutrality proposition. If we re-distribute from individual 2 to individual 1 there will be no change in final utility and all that happens will be that individual 2 cuts donations to the public good by the exact amount of the transfer, whereas individual 1 raises donations by the same amount. What does all this mean for Figure 5?
When there is a re-distribution the indifference curves must shift. Suppose say $10 is transferred from individual 2 to individual 1, and suppose 2 cuts donations to the public good by $10. In this case individual 1 would be as well off as before if she raised her contribution to the public good by $10. Now suppose we start at one particular point on 1’s indifference curve. After the transfer the equivalent point on 1’s new indifference map must be on the 450 line below and to the right of the old point (recall that individual 2 is lowering donations by $10, and 1 is raising them by the same amount). Our conclusion is:
When a transfer from 2 to 1 occurs on the diagram 1’s indifference map shifts down to the right along a 450 line.
A similar argument shows that 2’s indifference curve shifts down along the same 45o line, and by the same amount.
Armed with this conclusion, return to Figure 5. Suppose now we redistribute from individual 2 to individual 1. The indifference maps for the two individuals, and point A move down in a 450 line. As they do so the tangency going through point A follows. When point A reaches point B, the tangency as drawn goes through the origin. Hence if the re-distribution succeeds in moving point A to point B (or more precisely if the re-distribution ensures that the tangency goes through the origin), then the specified Pareto optimum can be achieved as a Lindahl equilibrium. As no matter which point we choose on the (dotted) line of Pareto optima, this will always be possible the second welfare theorem is proved for this sort of economy. To summarise
Theorem 2
Any specified Pareto optimum can be achieved as a Lindahl equilibrium.
Paradise regained it seems. However, things can’t be as easy as this, and although the Lindahl mechanism does indeed have a technical equivalence to the competitive mechanism, there are, even abstracting from the costs of operating the system a number of serious problems it faces in being implemented. We consider these in the next section.
5. The Incentive Problem
There are two points to make. One is rather technical, and just worth noting. The other is easier to understand and highlights a problem we shall take up later on in the module.
The (Non-shrinking) Core
In examining competitive equilibrium, mathematical economists developed the idea of the core. The concept itself is not too difficult to grasp. Suppose any set of agents was able to make any set of binding contracts they liked amongst themselves. What sort of allocation would result? The idea of the core results from the following observation. Suppose some allocation, call it A, is about to be realised as a result of a set of binding contracts individuals are about to make with one another. Suppose, however, that there exists a sub-set of individuals who can make a set of contracts amongst themselves that ensures they will all be better off than in A regardless of what the rest of the community does. In this case we would expect this subset to sign the relevant set of contracts. Allocation A would then not be realised. In thinking about what set of contracts people might agree upon, we should therefore require for that any set of contracts or allocation B to be a candidate for the final outcome for the economy, no such coalition should exist. That is, there should be no group of individuals who, by making a suitable set of contracts amongst themselves, can make themselves better off than they would be at B.
The set of allocations/contracts with this property is called the core of an economy. The interest of the core lies in its absence of any institutional detail, apart from the enforcement of contracts. If competitive allocations all lie inside the core we would expect them to have some sort of stability property. No group of individuals will be able to make alternative arrangements of mutual benefit to themselves. On the other hand, if allocations other than competitive ones lie in the core it is possible that outcomes other than the competitive ones are conceivable. So, given that people can make any set of contracts they like how do allocations in the core compare to the competitive allocations?
Using a box diagram it is easy to show that not all core allocations are competitive (starting from an initial endowment of goods). However, in 1963 Scarf and Debreu proved a result that had been suspected for some time. Take a private goods economy. As the number of individuals in the economy increases to infinity the set of core allocations shrinks to the set of competitive allocations.
Given that the Lindahl mechanism has an analogous role to the competitive mechanism for a public goods economy, it is natural to ask whether the same results hold. The answer is simple:
• Lindahl Equilibria allocations are in the core
• In general the core contains allocations other than Lindahl allocations
• The core does not shrink to the set of Lindahl allocations as community size expands
The analogy does therefore not go through completely, because of the last proposition. Intuitively, this can be understood in the following way. To eliminate an allocation from the core, there must exist a group of individuals who can make themselves better off regardless of what others in the community might do. In a private goods economy, the rest of the community can attempt to force some allocation of the “rogue” subgroup by refusing to trade with them, but this is the limit of what they can do. With a public good economy, the rest of the community has an extra weapon: they can refuse to supply any public goods (remember the rogue group will still benefit from any provision by the rest of the community). The extra sanctions available mean that other allocations are possible (Think for example of a Wicksell equilibrium that is not a Lindahl equilibrium).
This subsection is more in the nature of a footnote. We now turn to a more important point (for our purposes).
The Incentive Problem
Recall the way the Lindahl process works. People are asked to say how much of a public good they might want given the tax price (or Lindahl price) they face. To achieve the Pareto optimal outcome we must suppose that individuals are honest about how much G they want at each stage of the process. In this way the individual demands for the public good can be traced out accurately. But how plausible is that individuals will reply honestly? The answer is not very likely. Figure 6 illustrates.
Here we reproduce Figure 4 with the demand functions for individuals A and B. The Lindahl equilibrium is marked L, and individual A’s indifference curve at L is also drawn in. Remember that the direction of preference for A on the diagram is downwards. Other things being equal he wants to pay lower taxes. Individual B’s demand curve is drawn in. We can suppose she is being honest, but this is not needed. All we need is that B’s demand apparent curve is upward sloping, as drawn. Will A be honest? Suppose A responds to the government’s questions dishonestly, revealing the dotted line marked DA’ as his demand curve. If so the Lindahl process will end up at point Q. Given B’s declared demand curve, A has maximised utility reaching ICA’. For A, utility rises as a result of his dishonesty. It is also worth bearing in mind that A is being dishonest about something only he knows, so there is no danger of being caught out!
The conclusion is that there is no reason, apart from self-imposed morality, for individuals to behave honestly. This being so we would expect people to understate their preference for the public good (compare the false and true demand curves for A on Figure 6), and that if anything like a Lindahl process was ever used it would lead to under-provision of the public good.
6. Conclusion
The Lindahl mechanism can be looked at in a number of ways. In these notes we have focused on its role as public good analogue to the competitive mechanism for private goods. As such, it provides a notional ideal against which actual allocation mechanism can be measured. Although rather abstract, there are number of issues in taxation and political economy that it highlights.
Public Attitudes to Taxation
One key problem in determining the optimal level of government expenditure is the views the public or, from the politicians’ point of view, the electorate has on public goods. If say the question is about an expansion of health or education expenditure, what does the public want? In fact a common feature of opinion surveys is a form of schizophrenia on taxation. People value health, education etc., but are somewhat cagey about the question of taxation to pay for extra expenditure. A common response is: “Yes, I think extra expenditure on health is a good idea”. However, when asked about how this should be paid for, it is not uncommon to get the reply that “the rich” (i.e. someone else) should pay for it. This is unhelpful in working out what the optimum provision should be. Even with benign politicians, if we think the political process does in some remote way resemble the Lindahl model then there are going to be inefficiencies. The cause in this case is not dishonest politicians, but a dishonest electorate.
Not one key feature of the Lindahl model: government expenditure is linked directly to taxation. The only way you would get extra health-care expenditure in a Lindahl world is through being willing to pay for it, just as in an “ordinary” market.
Hypothecated Taxation
One proposal to overcome this problem is to hypothecate taxes. That is, to assign certain tax revenues to certain public expenditures. This is not common in the UK. Possible examples are the revenue from the road fund (car licence) which is supposed to go on road maintenance etc., and national insurance payments which finance the state pension and other social insurance benefits (job seekers’ benefit). In neither case is the link taken very seriously. More significantly, in the USA local elections are held to determine whether say a rise in sales tax should be enacted so as to finance extra expenditure on schools.
Whilst hypothecation is some way from a true Lindahl system, it is a step in that direction, and shares the key feature that tax and expenditure decisions are linked.
Implicit Lindahl Prices
Here we have not explored the political economy aspects of the Lindahl model in any detail. They are in any case a little diffuse. However, one insight from our analysis is worth mentioning. A key feature of most political systems is lobbying by various interest groups. This can take various forms, but often the lobbying is for some form of public provision of a good or service (which often does have some public characteristic). What determines who lobbies, and what sort of cause would they lobby for?
The Lindahl model gives us a clue as to where to start. If the government increases expenditure on say health, it will raise taxes to do so, or in Gordon Brown’s case national insurance contributions (usually taken to be a tax in practice). The point is that implicitly there is a price each person pays for the extra health expenditure. How does the net marginal benefit compare across individuals? Are there consistent differences between individuals we might expect, based perhaps on income levels?
There are many issues here. The Lindahl model does provide a basis for understanding the process of lobbying in democratic systems. Even when the system is not “democratic”, there are likely to be some albeit implicit interest groups. It would be foolish to suppose, though, that a Lindahl mechanism would end lobbying. It is true that given Lindahl prices no one would want to lobby for an extra amount of a public good. However, you do not need to pay more than casual attention to political debates to realise that much lobbying concerns taxation. A clear case of this was the fuel tax protests a few years ago, not to mention the debate over Ken Livingstone’s imposition of a road charge in London. Note, however, how the Lindahl model highlights the dishonest nature of much of this lobbying. “I want to pay lower taxes, so you (non-motorist or whoever) must pay more.” The second clause of the sentence is usually left out.
The point here is that much lobbying is for income distribution purposes. Under a Lindahl mechanism this problem emerges, as we have seen, in the incentive of individuals have to understate their preference for a public good. Hillman rightly places the Lindahl model at the centre of the economist’s attempt to understand the public sector, and refers to it as providing a “consensus” solution. It is unclear, though, how far we can take this idea if people are willing to use the “democratic” process to alter income distribution in their favour.
Pectus Excavatum
Our last lecture found out that voluntary action (the market mechanism) was likely to bring about a sub-optimal provision of the public good, as a result of individuals trying to take a free ride on the contributions of others. One obvious solution to this inefficiency is to recommend some form of government intervention. Indeed many of the services provided by governments have strong public good characteristics, and these are also important in areas in which the government intervenes rather than provides (e.g. environmental regulation). Defence, as we have seen, in many respects gets close to a pure public good, and the same can be said about “law and order”. The issue is rather more blurred with areas like education and health, but even so there are certainly some public good elements to what the government provides.
However, government provision of a public good raises a whole series of new questions. In fact it is a massive area of enquiry in its own right, in some respects incorporating political science. In this module we cannot hope here to do anything other than provide some basic ideas. The traditional starting point for economists in thinking about the public sector and in particular public expenditure is the Lindahl Model. In some ways this is a rather elusive concept, as it can be looked at in a variety of different ways:
• An alternative way of representing the Samuelson analysis
• A positive theory about how government expenditure decisions are arrived at
• A normative theory about how government expenditure should be arrived at
• An analytical device for judging alternative mechanisms by which government expenditure decisions are arrived at (somewhat similar to perfect competition in a world of private goods)
2. The Benefit Approach to Taxation
Modern public economics grew out of the old sub-discipline of public finance. A key issue in this older tradition concerned the concerned the basis of what could be called a fair tax. There were two approaches:
• The Benefit Approach. Here a fair tax was based the benefit an individual received from government expenditure. People who benefited more from public expenditure would, according to this school, have to incur a higher tax bill. This line of approach was particularly popular with continental economists, especially Italians and Scandinavians, although British thinkers adopted it in the 18th century stemming from a social contract view of the state.
• The Ability to Pay Approach. Here a just tax was based on an individual’s ability to pay. Those with a higher ability to pay should pay more taxes than those with a lower ability. This school of though was more popular in Anglo-Saxon countries, especially in the later 19th century possibly because of the stronger influence of utilitarian thinking.
Modern welfare economics has rather dispensed with debates of this kind, but both lines of thought have left their mark. The key idea of the benefit approach was that taxes should represent a payment for services delivered. The relationship of the government to the citizen was therefore one not in principle different from that between individuals in the community involved in mutually beneficial exchange. The state as such is only justified to the extent to which it provides benefits to individual citizens. The mainline value judgements adopted by modern welfare economics are Paretian, and the question of ultimate “justice” is not pursued any further than this. Taxes in the modern view are desirable if they lead to Pareto efficiency (subject to any distributive objectives about which Paretianism itself remains silent).
The benefit idea was revived by the Swedish economist Knut Wicksell in 1896, and in the hands of his pupil Lindahl, together with later developments led to a re-run of the Fundamental Theorems of welfare economics when public goods are present. Wicksell started from the following presumptions:
• People should not be coerced into paying for goods or services they do not want
• Public goods are more efficiently provided by the group as a whole, so individuals need to communicate their preferences to others
• To ensure that no coercion takes place, the appropriate principle a government must make in determining its expenditure-tax decisions is unanimity.
Although Wicksell wrote before the Paretian approach got established as the mainline form of welfare economics, his thinking fits very neatly into this approach. In a way, it represents an extreme form of Paretianism. When there are collective decisions to be made, how do we guarantee that no one is going to be made worse off? Unanimity (or giving each person a veto) would seem to be the only way. Wicksell realised, of course, that unanimity would be difficult in practice, but it was a principle to aim for, and in making decisions there should be “approximate unanimity”. The difficulties can be seen if we take another two person economy, and suppose individuals are bargaining over tax bills and provision of the public good. On Figure 1 we illustrate.
The area ABCD represents the area of Pareto improvement over the initial position without government. To see this note that the horizontal axis represents the provision of the public good, and the vertical individual A’s share of the total cost of whatever provision is decided upon. The indifference curve going through the origin represents the utility A receives in a state of anarchy (no government) (no taxes no government expenditure). With a veto over any decision A can be sure of never getting a utility level below this. The indifference curve going through the point (0, 1) fulfils a similar function for individual B.
The “model” of public expenditure determination goes as follows. The government announces a tax-expenditure package, say, point F. If both agents are better off than their initial position then they vote to accept this package, and point F is the next starting point. If the proposed package lies outside ABCD then at least one person will veto it, and it will be rejected. The government then produces another package. Starting from F another area of Pareto improvement can be traced out by the indifference curves going through F, and the government reformulates another package in the hope of finding another Pareto improvement. Once such a package has been found to which no one objects (vetoes) then this becomes the new starting point, and the process starts again. Equilibrium is finally reached when a package has been found for which for any counter proposal made there is always an objector. Such a point will be found somewhere on the set of Pareto optima, the dashed line (locus of tangencies) on Figure 1. It is not too difficult to show that tangency of the indifference curves on Figure is equivalent to the fulfilment of the Samuelson condition for Pareto optimality.
This, in simple terms is how the Wicksell model of ideal public expenditure should go. No one would argue for this to taken literally, but in a curious way it is quite instructive:
• Taken literally it is a process that guarantees Pareto optimality. However, its very artificiality may suggest that there are serious difficulties in the way of achieving this in practice.
• If each iteration is costly, as we would expect, then this would be a very expensive way of determining public expenditure
• Although stylised, the model picks up an important aspect of politics in modern democratic states. The determination of public expenditure is a major issue, as is the related determination of the tax burden. The process of determining these variables is accompanied by a lot of bargaining, both within and between government departments, and also, significantly, by lobbying by private interests
• Although Wicksell’s model is in a way within the benefit tradition, in one respect he is quite modern. He was careful to point out that his scheme was valid only once the question of the optimum distribution of income had been settled. Hence he separates out allocation and distributional questions in very much the same way as the fundamental theorems aim to do
• There is an obvious problem with the model even on its own terms. Why should people be honest in responding to successive government packages? Why pretend not to want the public good in an attempt to lower one’s own tax bill? This is a problem to which we shall return
• The final package (t, G) is indeterminate. We could end up anywhere on the line BD. There is no obvious way within the limits of the model to say where this might be. Incidentally, this point shows too that Wicksell’s point about income distribution has not been fully settled: the actual way this process proceeds could have quite significant implications for the distribution of welfare between individuals.
The Buchanan-Tullock Optimal Constitution
Wicksell’s idea proved quite influential, and, as is the way with these things, it developed in a number of differing ways. One such was the “optimal constitution” approach developed by Buchanan and Tullock in their 1962 book The Calculus of Consent. A central part of this book was an optimal voting scheme justified by unanimity. The idea was that while it would be too costly to rely on unanimity to reach every single tax-expenditure made by governments, the principle of unanimity could be preserved if everyone gave their consent to the process by which such decisions were made.
It is worth digressing a little to see this development of Wicksell’s idea. Buchanan and Tullock’s approach can be characterised in two ways:
• Like, Wicksell, they took Paretian value judgements seriously
• They consciously adopted a view of the state that revived the social contract tradition that originated in England in the 17th century.
The practical counterpart of their theory was the formation of the constitution of the United States in 1789.
Starting from Wicksell’s thinking they took it that Paretian value judgements should be treated seriously. No one should be coerced into submitting to laws or, for our purposes here, having to pay taxes without their consent. If we start from this point then in principle each person should have a veto over any law proposed, or any proposal to raise taxes, as with Wicksell. However, the cost of doing this is likely to be prohibitive, and probably going to satisfy no one. One country which did use the veto in its parliament (sejm) was Poland in the 17th and 18th centuries. This was hardly a good example of unanimity in action. The veto (liberum veto) was abolished in 1791 just four years before the country disappeared in a (final) partition between Austria, Prussia and Russia.
See Wikipedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sejm for some details.
Wishing for unanimity as a principle to underlie collective decisions, but recognising that it was impractical to have unanimity in every decision that has to be made, Buchanan and Tullock shifted the principle back one stage. People give their consent to each collective decision not if they approve of the decision itself, but if they have given their consent to the manner in which it was made. That is, everybody gives their consent to the “constitution”. This, as we have already seen, is to be thought of as the procedure by which this actual decisions (here most relevantly on taxation) are made. The picture they have is therefore quite parallel to the formation of the constitution of the USA, and, as a more recent possible example, to the establishment of democracy in the Eastern Europe.
This idea, though, raises the question of what sort of constitution would emerge from unanimous consent. Not much is said about the legal details in their book, but the principle by which decisions should be made is set out in the central chapter of the book, and illustrate on Figure 2 Here we have two cost functions. The decision-making function represents the cost of making a decision as determined by the percentage of individuals whose consent would be required. Quite possibly this becomes infinite as this approaches unanimity. The second function, the so-called “external cost” represents the possibility of lost of benefits from not being able to achieve Pareto optimality, or perhaps the expected cost of have a decision that makes the individual worse off. However we look at it, unanimity guarantees that no one will be made worse off or exploited by others, and it is reasonable to assume that this is downward sloping. Total cost is simply the sum of these two. So our individual would want a constitution that required the degree of consent given on the horizontal axis, the “optimal constitution”.
Various points can be made about this piece of analysis:
• If we think in terms of voting rules, the “optimal constitution” point could well vary as between the degree of consent required for different types of measure. It is notable, for example, that often a higher percentage of a vote is required for constitutional amendments.
• The schedules in Buchanan are not well defined. It is not clear what they mean in other than a very general sense.
• There is no reason why “majority rule” should have any special status as a voting scheme under this approach. This is argued by Buchanan and Tullock themselves, although they may overplay their hand because……..
• Voting rules that require more than 50% consent are not reversible. That it, they cannot be overturned by another coalition of voters. It 40% approve of a measure, then 40% could also vote to have it reversed. It is possible therefore that even though the schedules are ill-defined they have not been drawn accurately. There may be a jump in the decision-making function at 50%.
• In one sense Buchanan and Tullock do not solve the problem they pose. If our diagram represents what one individual thinks, there is no reason why the “optimal constitution” will not differ for another individual. It is not clear what happens at this point.
• One can regard the Buchanan-Tullock optimal constitution as an attempt to escape the dilemma of the Arrow Theorem. Unanimity might be easier to achieve for a constitution than for actual day-to-day decisions. However, there is no guarantee of this within the framework B-T develop.
• Buchanan and Tullock compound this last problem by asserting that at the constitutional stage people have already established a set of property rights. They negotiate about the constitution on this basis. This makes the possibility of unanimity less likely. To take the US example, an unpleasant one, it is reasonable to suppose that slaves in the 18th century USA would, had they been asked, have expressed rather different views about the constitution from the slave owners who were instrumental in writing the constitution.
• One can interpret Rawls’ 1971 A Theory of Justice as a way of clearing up this obscurity in B-T. His view was that a constitution should be based on what individuals would agree to behind a veil of ignorance. That is, people would know how society would be run, what laws and rules it would have, but would not know their identity within that society. They would have an equal chance of being any “named” individual. So they could be a slave owner, if it were a case of joining 18th century USA, but it would be much more likely that to be a slave. Who would consent to slavery in this case? Behind the veil of ignorance, it becomes more plausible that unanimity could be achieved. We could therefore interpret Rawls as trying to find a way round the Arrow problem
Another approach which leads into modern general equilibrium theory was initiated by Wicksell’s fellow Swede Erik Lindahl. To this we now turn.
3. The Lindahl Model: Two Person Economy
Lindahl’s work published in 1919 refined that of Wicksell. We can get an idea of the key points by looking again at the Wicksell diagram. Consider Figure 3. The indifference map is reproduced as in Figure 1, but now individuals are asked a different question. Instead of “Do you approve this total tax-expenditure package?” they are asked, “If you had to pay x% of the tax bill what quantity of the public good would you want to see provided?” Although the fundamental features of the Wicksell approach are preserved, there are one or two significant differences in the way we can look at the model. The key difference is that after setting personal tax rates the government/planners look at the responses individual make. If people are unanimous then the process stops and the tax rates and provision of the public good are determined accordingly. If people are not unanimous, then the government adjusts tax rates and puts the question again to the electorate. A natural procedure would be to raise the tax rates for those who want a high provision of the public good, and lower the tax rate for those who want low provision. The process continues until people are unanimous.
To see how this might work out, first imagine we alter the share of tax that individual A must pay, and trace out her responses. This we do on Figure 3. Clearly, as the tax share falls in some sense the price of the public good to our individual must also fall. Hence by tracing out the locus of tangencies as we do we must derive some sort of a demand curve for the public good. We can repeat this procedure for individual B. As lowering tA means tB = 1 – tA must rise the demand curve we draw will be upward sloping. The result is shown on Figure 4. Naturally something significant must be happening at the point at which the two demand curves intersect. This point indeed represents the (unique) Lindahl equilibrium on the diagram where people are unanimous about how much of the public good should be provided. Various comments follow…
• The significance of the intersection is that again as with Wicksell individuals are unanimous about the tax expenditure package. However, in this case the unanimity takes a slightly different form. Given the tax shares no one wants to alter the quantity of the public good. If you could imagine this in a political system, this could be interpreted as meaning that no one would want to lobby to alter the level of government expenditure.
• This last point can be illustrated by drawing in the indifference curves for point L, the Lindahl equilibrium on Figure 4. Given the way the demand curves were constructed, not only will we have tangency but the each indifference curve will be horizontal at this point. Given the tax share, each person consumes exactly the quantity of the public good they would want to consume. With Wicksell it is possible to have an equilibrium in which one person would want more G given their tax share, and their partner less (Draw a diagram to confirm this point).
• Suppose, to keep life simple, we have a constant cost economy, so the public good price, pG, is fixed. If the tax share for individual is tA then the expression tApG represents the effective price of the public good for individual A. A similar point applies to B. (The assumption of constant cost is not essential to this argument. These personalised prices can simply be defined in the same way for a variable cost economy. In this case it might perhaps be better to refer to t as the cost share rather than the share of the tax bill).
• The “personalised prices” are referred to a Lindahl Prices. Usually the writer uses this term to refer to the equilibrium prices, but this semantic issue is not important. The key point is that with (equilibrium) Lindahl prices individuals get exactly the quantity of the public good that they would choose if they had to pay their Lindahl price. In practice, of course, people cannot choose the quantity of a public good in the same way as they do the quantity of a private good. However, the Lindahl model produces an outcome in which things are no different from what they would be if individuals had this choice.
• This last point means that there is a sense in which the Lindahl model converts a public good economy to one which is analytically equivalent to a private good economy.
This being the case, a natural question to ask is whether the Lindahl model has the equivalent of the two Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics. That is, is it the case that all Lindahl equilibria are Pareto optimal? And is it also true that any specified Pareto optimum can be realised as a Lindahl equilibrium? Not only do the last couple of points suggest the questions, they also suggest a way of answering them. For if a notional equivalence between a Lindahl economy and a private goods economy can be established then the proofs of the original fundamental theorems can be used to shown that the Lindahl model is the public goods analogue of the competitive mechanism for a private goods economy.
4. The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics Revisited
It is easy to show that at any Lindahl equilibrium the Samuelson condition must hold:
Given the replication property referred to in the last section, at any Lindahl equilibrium, and given any individual i, with a private good x and a public good G, the following condition must hold:
pG is the actual price paid for delivery of the public good. We assume that the public good is produced by competitive firms. Hence:
Now sum this equation over all n individuals:
This is the Samuelson condition.
Technically, however, this does not provide us with a proof of the first Fundamental condition. The Samuelson condition is a necessary, not a sufficient, condition for a Pareto optimum. However, this argument suggests, correctly, that in all standard cases the analogue of the first theorem holds. In fact under pretty much the same conditions as with a private good economy we have:
Theorem 1
Any Lindahl Equilibrium is Pareto Optimal.
The second theorem is a bit more difficult, but in its technical details the proof goes through in pretty much the same way as the original theorem. The key technical assumption is again convexity, which is needed to ensure the existence of a set of (Lindahl) prices. Once these have been found, then utility and profit maximisation do the rest of the work. We can show the second theorem diagrammatically using the diagram developed by Cornes and Sandler, Figure 5.
The dotted line in this diagram is a 45o line, and the line AC is the set of Pareto Optima. Our problem is this. Can we specify any point on AC, and then (at least in principle) achieve this point as a Lindahl equilibrium?
Assuming constant cost, a Lindahl set of prices for this economy would be shown as a straight line going through the origin. (Individuals pay a fixed share of whatever it is that is delivered). Suppose we are interested in reaching point A. As the diagram shows, the tangent going through point A does not go through the origin. Hence if we are to reach point A some prior redistribution must occur. To see how this happens on the diagram, recall the Warr Neutrality proposition. If we re-distribute from individual 2 to individual 1 there will be no change in final utility and all that happens will be that individual 2 cuts donations to the public good by the exact amount of the transfer, whereas individual 1 raises donations by the same amount. What does all this mean for Figure 5?
When there is a re-distribution the indifference curves must shift. Suppose say $10 is transferred from individual 2 to individual 1, and suppose 2 cuts donations to the public good by $10. In this case individual 1 would be as well off as before if she raised her contribution to the public good by $10. Now suppose we start at one particular point on 1’s indifference curve. After the transfer the equivalent point on 1’s new indifference map must be on the 450 line below and to the right of the old point (recall that individual 2 is lowering donations by $10, and 1 is raising them by the same amount). Our conclusion is:
When a transfer from 2 to 1 occurs on the diagram 1’s indifference map shifts down to the right along a 450 line.
A similar argument shows that 2’s indifference curve shifts down along the same 45o line, and by the same amount.
Armed with this conclusion, return to Figure 5. Suppose now we redistribute from individual 2 to individual 1. The indifference maps for the two individuals, and point A move down in a 450 line. As they do so the tangency going through point A follows. When point A reaches point B, the tangency as drawn goes through the origin. Hence if the re-distribution succeeds in moving point A to point B (or more precisely if the re-distribution ensures that the tangency goes through the origin), then the specified Pareto optimum can be achieved as a Lindahl equilibrium. As no matter which point we choose on the (dotted) line of Pareto optima, this will always be possible the second welfare theorem is proved for this sort of economy. To summarise
Theorem 2
Any specified Pareto optimum can be achieved as a Lindahl equilibrium.
Paradise regained it seems. However, things can’t be as easy as this, and although the Lindahl mechanism does indeed have a technical equivalence to the competitive mechanism, there are, even abstracting from the costs of operating the system a number of serious problems it faces in being implemented. We consider these in the next section.
5. The Incentive Problem
There are two points to make. One is rather technical, and just worth noting. The other is easier to understand and highlights a problem we shall take up later on in the module.
The (Non-shrinking) Core
In examining competitive equilibrium, mathematical economists developed the idea of the core. The concept itself is not too difficult to grasp. Suppose any set of agents was able to make any set of binding contracts they liked amongst themselves. What sort of allocation would result? The idea of the core results from the following observation. Suppose some allocation, call it A, is about to be realised as a result of a set of binding contracts individuals are about to make with one another. Suppose, however, that there exists a sub-set of individuals who can make a set of contracts amongst themselves that ensures they will all be better off than in A regardless of what the rest of the community does. In this case we would expect this subset to sign the relevant set of contracts. Allocation A would then not be realised. In thinking about what set of contracts people might agree upon, we should therefore require for that any set of contracts or allocation B to be a candidate for the final outcome for the economy, no such coalition should exist. That is, there should be no group of individuals who, by making a suitable set of contracts amongst themselves, can make themselves better off than they would be at B.
The set of allocations/contracts with this property is called the core of an economy. The interest of the core lies in its absence of any institutional detail, apart from the enforcement of contracts. If competitive allocations all lie inside the core we would expect them to have some sort of stability property. No group of individuals will be able to make alternative arrangements of mutual benefit to themselves. On the other hand, if allocations other than competitive ones lie in the core it is possible that outcomes other than the competitive ones are conceivable. So, given that people can make any set of contracts they like how do allocations in the core compare to the competitive allocations?
Using a box diagram it is easy to show that not all core allocations are competitive (starting from an initial endowment of goods). However, in 1963 Scarf and Debreu proved a result that had been suspected for some time. Take a private goods economy. As the number of individuals in the economy increases to infinity the set of core allocations shrinks to the set of competitive allocations.
Given that the Lindahl mechanism has an analogous role to the competitive mechanism for a public goods economy, it is natural to ask whether the same results hold. The answer is simple:
• Lindahl Equilibria allocations are in the core
• In general the core contains allocations other than Lindahl allocations
• The core does not shrink to the set of Lindahl allocations as community size expands
The analogy does therefore not go through completely, because of the last proposition. Intuitively, this can be understood in the following way. To eliminate an allocation from the core, there must exist a group of individuals who can make themselves better off regardless of what others in the community might do. In a private goods economy, the rest of the community can attempt to force some allocation of the “rogue” subgroup by refusing to trade with them, but this is the limit of what they can do. With a public good economy, the rest of the community has an extra weapon: they can refuse to supply any public goods (remember the rogue group will still benefit from any provision by the rest of the community). The extra sanctions available mean that other allocations are possible (Think for example of a Wicksell equilibrium that is not a Lindahl equilibrium).
This subsection is more in the nature of a footnote. We now turn to a more important point (for our purposes).
The Incentive Problem
Recall the way the Lindahl process works. People are asked to say how much of a public good they might want given the tax price (or Lindahl price) they face. To achieve the Pareto optimal outcome we must suppose that individuals are honest about how much G they want at each stage of the process. In this way the individual demands for the public good can be traced out accurately. But how plausible is that individuals will reply honestly? The answer is not very likely. Figure 6 illustrates.
Here we reproduce Figure 4 with the demand functions for individuals A and B. The Lindahl equilibrium is marked L, and individual A’s indifference curve at L is also drawn in. Remember that the direction of preference for A on the diagram is downwards. Other things being equal he wants to pay lower taxes. Individual B’s demand curve is drawn in. We can suppose she is being honest, but this is not needed. All we need is that B’s demand apparent curve is upward sloping, as drawn. Will A be honest? Suppose A responds to the government’s questions dishonestly, revealing the dotted line marked DA’ as his demand curve. If so the Lindahl process will end up at point Q. Given B’s declared demand curve, A has maximised utility reaching ICA’. For A, utility rises as a result of his dishonesty. It is also worth bearing in mind that A is being dishonest about something only he knows, so there is no danger of being caught out!
The conclusion is that there is no reason, apart from self-imposed morality, for individuals to behave honestly. This being so we would expect people to understate their preference for the public good (compare the false and true demand curves for A on Figure 6), and that if anything like a Lindahl process was ever used it would lead to under-provision of the public good.
6. Conclusion
The Lindahl mechanism can be looked at in a number of ways. In these notes we have focused on its role as public good analogue to the competitive mechanism for private goods. As such, it provides a notional ideal against which actual allocation mechanism can be measured. Although rather abstract, there are number of issues in taxation and political economy that it highlights.
Public Attitudes to Taxation
One key problem in determining the optimal level of government expenditure is the views the public or, from the politicians’ point of view, the electorate has on public goods. If say the question is about an expansion of health or education expenditure, what does the public want? In fact a common feature of opinion surveys is a form of schizophrenia on taxation. People value health, education etc., but are somewhat cagey about the question of taxation to pay for extra expenditure. A common response is: “Yes, I think extra expenditure on health is a good idea”. However, when asked about how this should be paid for, it is not uncommon to get the reply that “the rich” (i.e. someone else) should pay for it. This is unhelpful in working out what the optimum provision should be. Even with benign politicians, if we think the political process does in some remote way resemble the Lindahl model then there are going to be inefficiencies. The cause in this case is not dishonest politicians, but a dishonest electorate.
Not one key feature of the Lindahl model: government expenditure is linked directly to taxation. The only way you would get extra health-care expenditure in a Lindahl world is through being willing to pay for it, just as in an “ordinary” market.
Hypothecated Taxation
One proposal to overcome this problem is to hypothecate taxes. That is, to assign certain tax revenues to certain public expenditures. This is not common in the UK. Possible examples are the revenue from the road fund (car licence) which is supposed to go on road maintenance etc., and national insurance payments which finance the state pension and other social insurance benefits (job seekers’ benefit). In neither case is the link taken very seriously. More significantly, in the USA local elections are held to determine whether say a rise in sales tax should be enacted so as to finance extra expenditure on schools.
Whilst hypothecation is some way from a true Lindahl system, it is a step in that direction, and shares the key feature that tax and expenditure decisions are linked.
Implicit Lindahl Prices
Here we have not explored the political economy aspects of the Lindahl model in any detail. They are in any case a little diffuse. However, one insight from our analysis is worth mentioning. A key feature of most political systems is lobbying by various interest groups. This can take various forms, but often the lobbying is for some form of public provision of a good or service (which often does have some public characteristic). What determines who lobbies, and what sort of cause would they lobby for?
The Lindahl model gives us a clue as to where to start. If the government increases expenditure on say health, it will raise taxes to do so, or in Gordon Brown’s case national insurance contributions (usually taken to be a tax in practice). The point is that implicitly there is a price each person pays for the extra health expenditure. How does the net marginal benefit compare across individuals? Are there consistent differences between individuals we might expect, based perhaps on income levels?
There are many issues here. The Lindahl model does provide a basis for understanding the process of lobbying in democratic systems. Even when the system is not “democratic”, there are likely to be some albeit implicit interest groups. It would be foolish to suppose, though, that a Lindahl mechanism would end lobbying. It is true that given Lindahl prices no one would want to lobby for an extra amount of a public good. However, you do not need to pay more than casual attention to political debates to realise that much lobbying concerns taxation. A clear case of this was the fuel tax protests a few years ago, not to mention the debate over Ken Livingstone’s imposition of a road charge in London. Note, however, how the Lindahl model highlights the dishonest nature of much of this lobbying. “I want to pay lower taxes, so you (non-motorist or whoever) must pay more.” The second clause of the sentence is usually left out.
The point here is that much lobbying is for income distribution purposes. Under a Lindahl mechanism this problem emerges, as we have seen, in the incentive of individuals have to understate their preference for a public good. Hillman rightly places the Lindahl model at the centre of the economist’s attempt to understand the public sector, and refers to it as providing a “consensus” solution. It is unclear, though, how far we can take this idea if people are willing to use the “democratic” process to alter income distribution in their favour.
Pectus Excavatum
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)